Module 5A Flashcards
Argument Construction and Refutation:
Argument construction often starts with attempting to refute someone else’s view, often using more elaborate methods than simple counterexamples.
Common Refutation Method:
One common and powerful method of refutation involving argument construction is reductio ad absurdum.
Reductio ad Absurdum:
Briefly described by Govier on pp. 248.
- An argumentative technique that aims to demonstrate the falsity of a proposition by showing that its logical consequence leads to an absurd or contradictory result.
- Reductio ad absurdum involves constructing a detailed argument to show that if a particular proposition were true, it would lead to absurd or contradictory conclusions.
Power of Reductio ad Absurdum:
A powerful technique that goes beyond simple counterexamples and aims to expose inherent contradictions or absurdities in a given viewpoint.
Argument by reductio relies on modus tollens and conditionalisation. The principle involves the following steps:
- P [prem.: provisional assumption]
- Q [prem.: any non-provisional assumptions, displayed as a conjunction]
- Q & P [2 & 1, conjunction]
- C [3, consequence of P and any other premisses Q]
- If Q & P, then C [3 & 4, conditionalisation]
- Not-C [obvious ex hypothesi]
- Not-(Q & P) [5 & 6, modus tollens]
- Not-Q or not-P [7, distributing the negation]
- Not-not-Q [2, double negation]
- Not-P [8 & 9, disjunctive syllogism]
Role of ‘P’ and ‘C’:
‘P’ indicates the statement targeted for refutation (the first provisional premiss).
‘C’ indicates any obviously false conclusion derived from conjoining P with other non-provisional assumption[s] (Q).
Unquestioned Truth of ‘Q’:
Truth of Q is unquestioned and meant to outweigh P in a choice between them.
A version of Revised Standard Form is used to display more information than in the notes Lecture 3A
Risk in Reductio ad Absurdum
Reductio ad absurdum carries the risk that if someone accepts P but admits that C is obviously false, they might reject P and attribute the issue to one or more other assumptions labeled as ‘Q.’
The proponent of the reductio offers Q as outweighing P, but this offer may be rejected.
Identifying the Cause of Trouble:
A reductio does not on its own indicate which premiss is the cause of the trouble.
Broad vs. Narrow Sense of ‘Reductio’:
The argument-form uses a broad sense of ‘reductio’ where the derived consequence C only needs to be obviously false.
In the narrow sense used by Govier, C must be an explicit contradiction.
Conclusiveness:
An argument leading to an explicit contradiction is more conclusive than one leading to an ‘obviously false’ statement.
Explicit contradictions are universally rejected, while opinions may differ on statements labeled as ‘obviously false.’
Argumentum ad Hominem
Argumentum ad hominem refers to an argument that targets the person holding a particular view (‘P’) rather than addressing the view itself.
Relation to Reductio: Argumentum ad Hominem:
The presentation of argument by reductio as a strategy against a person holding a view connects it to argumentum ad hominem.
Ad Hominem Definition:
Ad hominem means ‘against the man,’ implying an attack on the person rather than engaging with the substance of their argument.
Dependency on Conditionalisation and Modus Tollens:
Ad hominem
Ad hominem arguments can depend on the moves of conditionalisation and modus tollens
Example in Plato’s Euthyphro:
Example: Sections 6D–9B of Plato’s Euthyphro contain a powerful ad hominem argument where Socrates demonstrates the inconsistency in Euthyphro’s action of prosecuting his father for impiety based on Euthyphro’s own definition of piety.
Consequence for Euthyphro:
The consequence for Euthyphro is that, if he cannot find an objection to Socrates’s argument and wants to be consistent, he must either abandon the prosecution, abandon his account of piety, or face prosecution himself.
Here is another powerful example:
Argumentum ad hominem
Foxhunting ought to be abolished; it is cruel to the victim and degrading to the participants.
A .
Foxhunting ought to be abolished; it is cruel to the victim and degrading to the participants.
B .
But you eat meat; and you never worry about whether the killing of the animals you eat is cruel to them and degrading to the butchers.
B’s argument, spelled out in somewhat non-standard form, goes as follows:
- Foxhunting is cruel to victim and degrading to participants [accepted by A]
- Killing of animals for food is not relevantly different from foxhunting [claim added by B]
So,
- Both ought to be abolished [consistent with A’s original inference]
So,
- If 1 and 2 are true, then 3 is true [conditionalisation]
- But A cannot accept 3 [since A eats meat]
Hence,
- A cannot consistently accept 1 and 2 [4 & 5, by modus tollens]
****Assuming that A is moved by the requirement of consistency, this leaves him with a difficult choice
of responses:
- A must abandon 1;
- or show that 2 is false;
- or accept 3 and (presumably) stop eating
meat
Not all ad hominem arguments are equally powerful. Here’s an example of a weaker one:
Example of a Weaker Ad Hominem:
Argument: Disregard Hegel’s views on women because of his unsatisfactory breast relationship with his mother, influencing his perspective on women throughout his life.
- Weakness of the Argument:
– The degree of support for this ad hominem argument is weak, and it lacks completeness. - Not Entirely Negligible:
– Despite its weak support, the argument is not entirely negligible. - Fair Warning:
– The argument, if its premises are true, provides fair warning that there might be issues with Hegel’s views on women. - Separating Rationality and Correctness:
– Acknowledges that even if Hegel’s views were irrationally formed, they could still be correct. The ad hominem doesn’t necessarily invalidate the correctness of the views but suggests caution due to potential biases.
Ad Hominem in Standard Logic Textbooks:
Standard logic textbooks categorize argumentum ad hominem as a fallacy to be avoided.
Variety in Ad Hominem Arguments:
Ad hominem covers a wide range of arguments with varying degrees of support.
Focus of Ad Hominem:
Ad hominem arguments don’t prove a specific statement false; instead, they attack something about a person.
Govier’s View on Ad Hominem:
Govier’s discussion (pp. 157–60) may suggest that she sees ad hominem as always fallacious, but upon closer examination, she acknowledges the diversity in ad hominem arguments.
Degrees of Support:
ad hominem arguments
Govier shares the view that some ad hominem arguments are good, while others are bad, similar to how the quality of arguments in other forms varies.
Circumstantial Ad Hominem:
Govier treats the circumstantial ad hominem as always fallacious, but this stance ignores the complexities revealed through examples like Euthyphro.
Questioning Govier’s Interpretation:
Ad Hominem:
When reading p. 158, questions arise about Govier’s interpretation of Lowe’s argument against Szasz’s theory.
Was Lowe arguing that Szasz’s theory is false, or was he making a different point?