Topic 8 - Incapacity and General Defences - Theory Flashcards

You may prefer our related Brainscape-certified flashcards:
1
Q

Defining defences - traditional approach

A

> Some defences, e.g. loss of control, mitigate sentence imposed & don’t actually lead to acquittal.
P. Robinson suggests defences are ‘anything that prevents conviction of a defendent.’ But Husak says this is too wide as it would include death of D before trial is complete.
Traditional classification of defences:
1. AR of crime
2. MR of crime
3. A defence
4. Mitigation.
Glanville Williams: “what we think of as the definition of an offence and what we call a defence can only be regarded as depending largely upon the accidents of language, the convenience of legal drafter, or the unreasoning force of tradition.”
Husak: can be hard to tell which category a matter falls in to.
But just because ‘bright lines’ can’t be drawn, it doesn’t mean the classification isn’t useful.
Self-defence, automatism = denial of AR.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
2
Q

Defining defences - alternatives to the traditional classification

A
  1. Add additional category of exemption:
    - Lacey = those who are outside the purview of the criminal law.
    - Horder = such people can’t be required to comply with the standards expected of the criminal law because they lack the capacity to appreciate those standards or be responsible for their behaviour.
    - E.g. children & insane but Loughnan & P. Robinson are sceptical about exemptions. Argue that although someone may be insane at time of offence, they may not generally be insane and so to describe such person as exempt from the criminal law sometimes &sometimes not creates unnecessary confusion.
  2. Argue that all defences are in essence about redefining the offence definition (P. Robinson):
    - All offences made up of just 2 elements (AR and MR) and all defences would be denials of AR or MR.
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
3
Q

Defining defences - does any of this matter?

A

> There are cases where distinctions have practical significance.
In offences of SL, where there’s no need for prosecution to prove any MR, whether an element is regarded as of AR or MR is important.
Prosecution have burden of proving AR and MR elements of the offence whilst the defence carries the burden of raising the defence so whether self-defence is a denial of AR or a defence matters.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
4
Q

Justifications & excuses - overview

A

> One popular way to analyse between defences is to distinguish between justifications & excuses.
P. Robinson: “An actor’s conduct is justified, an actor is excused.”
Justification focuses on what D did and claims that what they did was permitted by the law normally because society has approved of what they have done.
With an excuse, D admits that what they did wasn’t permissible, but that they don’t deserve to be blamed. E.g. because of their mental state.
Nicola Lacey:
-“While excuses bear primarily on the conditions of circumstances under which D has acted, and hence on responsibility, justifications bear on the nature of D’s conduct.”
-“Justifications justify actions; excuses excuse actors.”
-However, the “distinction turns out, once again, to be a difficult line to hold.”
-“First, justificatory and excusatory elements are often blended in actual defense arguments.”
-“Second, even where a defense is placed on a firmly excusatory footing, evaluations of reasonableness come into play.”
-“A provoked reaction must be that of a ‘reasonable person’; the duress defense is available only where a person of ‘reasonable firmness’ would have succumbed to the threat, and so on.”
-“Generally entitled to be judged on the basis of the facts as they believed them to be.”

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
5
Q

Justifications & excuses - justifications

A

> Fletcher discusses the debate concerning justification which concerns whether, if there is a justification, there is still a wrong committed against a V.
One view is that D has still wronged the ‘V’, but that this wrong has been outweighed by the good consequences flowing from the act whilst the opposite view is that if the act is justified then it is ‘all right’ and no legal wrong has been done.
Preferable to say that a justification involves actions that are permissible, rather than actions that are right although Uniacke suggests a distinction between a strong justification (the act was morally right) and a weak justification (the act was permissible, although morally wrong).
How does law decide if what D did is permissible if it would otherwise be a criminal offence?
1. Lesser of two evils.
2. Moral forfeiture.
3. Securing legal & moral rights.
4. Public authority justification.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
6
Q

Justifications & excuses - justifications - How does law decide if what D did is permissible if it would otherwise be a criminal offence? Lesser of 2 evils

A

> P. Robinson: no ‘net societal harm.’

>Alexander: doesn’t explain why it’s permissible to use slightly more force than is threatened to repel an attack.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
7
Q

Justifications & excuses - justifications - How does law decide if what D did is permissible if it would otherwise be a criminal offence? Moral forfeiture

A

> Leverick: V forfeited right not to be injured as a result of their morally wrong conduct, thereby authorising D’s use of force against them.
Some commentators argue fundamental rights shouldn’t be forfeited.
Theory works well unless V isn’t morally to blame.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
8
Q

Justifications & excuses - justifications - How does law decide if what D did is permissible if it would otherwise be a criminal offence? securing legal & moral rights

A

> D is acting in order to promote their legal (and moral) rights.
Protect/promoted right to personal autonomy.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
9
Q

Justifications & excuses - justifications - How does law decide if what D did is permissible if it would otherwise be a criminal offence?

A

> Public officers are given authority on behalf of state to use force in certain circumstances.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
10
Q

The Dadson view

A

> View taken in English law following Dadson 1850 that only if one acts in a permissible way and for justifying reasons can one claim to be justified.
Hitchler adds that the justifying circumstances must be one of the reasons for which D acted.
Don’t want people to break the law if they aren’t aware of any justifying circumstances.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
11
Q

Justifications & excuses - justifications - deeds vs reasons

A

> Fundamental dispute over the nature of justification.
A person is justified because:
-Their deeds are justified (the ‘deeds’ view).
-They act for justifiable reasons (the ‘reasons’ view).
-Both their deeds and reasons are justified (the ‘deeds and reasons’ view).

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
12
Q

Justifications & excuses - excuses

A

> Kadish: excuses are all about removing the blame.
Marcia Baron suggests excuses can be divided into 2 categories:
1. Those that relate to D & claim that there was something about D which made it harder for them than most people to comply with the law and;
2. Those that relate to the circumstances D founds themselves in.
Excuses therefore complete the picture of assessment of D’s blameworthiness.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
13
Q

Justifications & excuses - excuses - essential elements of an excuse

A

> J. Horder, Excusing Crime:

  • “It is a necessary condition of any claim to excuse that it is an explanation for engagement in wrongdoing”
  • “Excuses are morally as well as legally distinctive in character. Excuses excuse the act or omission amounting to wrongdoing, by shedding favourable moral light on what D did.”
  • “Morally active”
  • “Finding an understandable ‘rational defect’ in a morally salient motivating force of factor behind an action is perhaps the most commonly encountered route to excuse, particularly, but not solely, where the action is grounded in a strong emotional reaction.”
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
14
Q

Does the distinction between justifications and excuses really matter?

A
  1. Paul Robinson suggests that if the law provides justification this in effect changes the law.
    - If say shooting someone is justified the law would change to the extent that it was lawful to shoot someone in ‘X’ circumstance.
    - Whereas if D is granted an excuse then as no 2 people are identical, the fact one person was excused doesn’t mean another will be.
    - Although once a particular medical condition gives rise to a defence then could argue all sufferers are likely to use the excuse.
    - Horder: justification seeks to offer guidance to Ds before they act, while excuses assess the culpability of the offenders one they have acted.
  2. If D is attacked by a person who is excused, D can lawfully resist the attack but if person using force against D is justified, he cannot.
    - Gur-Ayre suggests a person’s right to self-defence shouldn’t be lost even if the attack they are facing is justified or excused.
  3. You can lawfully assist a person who is justified in using force, but not someone who is only excused.
    - Gury-Ayre also rejects this on the basis that a person intervening to protect someone’s life should have a legal defence irrespective of whether the person whose life they are saving is justified or an excused act.
  4. Some commentators suggest that a defendant who, through their own fault, puts themself in a position where they must choose between the lesser of 2 evils can rely on justification, but an excuse isn’t available for a person who had brought about their own excusing state of mind.
    - Contested by some who argue a justification shouldn’t be available where D has acted for the purpose of putting himself in the position where he has to choose between 2 evils.
  5. Robinson recommends that when jury acquits D they should be required to make it clear if it was because they were excused, justified or failed to establish MR or AR so the basis of D’s acquittal is clarified and law is able to send a clear message about the requirements of the criminal law.
  6. Debate over whether legal test for justification is objective and excuse subjective but this is rarely so.
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
15
Q

Should justifications be objective & excuses subjective?

A

> At first sight, justification = objective and excuse = subjective but defences often involve a mix of objective & subjective elements.
Robinson view of justifications = purely objective however, Dadson view requires some objectivity as D’s state of mind is relevant too (D needs to be aware of & acted because of the justificatory reasons.)
Controversy over whether all excuses should be purely subjective. E.g. should duress be whether D felt compelled by the threat or whether the reasonable person would have? Although if regard duress as justification then no issue here.
Horder argues that there is a justificatory element in excuses.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
16
Q

Justifications & Excuses - J. Gardner - summary

A

> J. Gardner argues there is a closer relationship between justifications & reasons than is often supposed.
He suggests the reasons must be guiding or explanatory.
Guiding = reasons which dictate what you ought to do or believe.
Explanatory = explain why you act in a particular way.
A person may think their explanatory reasons are guiding reasons but they might not be.
Gardner argues that to amount to a justification a person must have both guiding & explanatory reasons for being justified, and the guiding reason must correspond with the explanatory reason.
An excuse, he argues, is analogous to a justification in that an excused person must act for good explanatory reasons and then justify why there thought they were justified.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
17
Q

J. Gardner, ‘Justifications and Reasons’ - passage

A

> It is widely thought that excuses are more ‘subjective’ than justifications. In one sense of ‘subjective’, as we will see, this is perfectly true. But it is not true if we are using the labels ‘subjective’ & ‘objective’ to mark the contrast between explanatory & guiding reasons.
Whenever excuses depend on the union of explanatory and guiding reasons, moreover, they do so precisely because justifications depend on the union of explanatory and guiding reasons.
The structure of excuse derives, in other words, from the structure of justification, and thus shares in its combination of subjective (explanatory) and objective (guiding) rationality.
Theorists who think every excuse is concerned with character traits are mistaken.
A fully justified actions needs no excuse so the point must be that there is something suspect about the reasons for which they act. And indeed there is. They are not valid reasons. They are what the person acting upon them takes to be valid reasons, and justifiably so. Thus the structure of excuse derives from the structure of justification. To excuse an action is not, of course, to justify that action. Rather, one justifies one’s belief that the action is justified.
Emotions like anger and fear are mediating forces between beliefs and actions. They enhance or constrain the motivating force of certain motivating beliefs. Their justification therefore turns in part on the justification of the beliefs which partly constitute them, Of course there is still a justificatory gap: an emotion is not fully justified merely by the justification of its cognitive component. But justified emotion nevertheless entails justified belief.
One must therefore consider what is needed to make a belief justified.
A belief is justified, not only by the reasons there are for holding it, but also by the process of reasoning by which it came to be held, i.e., not only by guiding reasons but also by explanatory reasons.
Excuses, in which an element of reasonableness, at some level, is conceptually necessitated whether the crime is one of full subjective MR or one of no MR at all.
Requirements of ‘reasonableness’ in criminal excuses serve to orientate the law towards general application to people living many different forms of life, rather than tailoring it to suit the expected virtues of a certain kind of person leading a certain kind of life. The debate about the extent to which the reasonable person should be ‘individualised’ to the characteristics of the defendant in the definition of criminal excuses is partly a debate about the extent to which the criminal law should aspire to this kind of generality.
Legal systems can vary in their willingness to individualise excuses and general principles but they cannot altogether eliminate the essential ‘objective’ dimension if excusatory claims because excuses rely on reason and not the absence of it.
Justification and excuse both belong to the realm of responsible agency, and that is precisely because both depend on the ability to live with reason.
Between the concepts of justification and excuse, justification is the more fundamental. The same proposition also brings out the true sense in which excuses may be regarded as more ‘subjective’ than justifications. For by their nature excuses take the world as the defendant justifiably sees it rather than as it is. They look to what the defendant believes to be applicable reasons for action, so long as she does so on the basis of genuinely applicable reasons for belief. Justifications, meanwhile, look directly to the genuinely applicable reasons for action, without stopping to look for applicable reasons for belief. But in this whole contrast the talk of ‘reasons’ is talk of guiding reasons. It leaves on one side the fact that, in both justification and excuse, explanatory reasons also play a key role, and that, in this sense and to this extent, each is just as subjected as the other.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
18
Q

Problems with justifications and excuses

A

> Reasons for denial of usefulness in the distinction:

  1. General refusal of the courts to engage in an analysis of the defences in terms of justifications and excuses may indicate the distinction lacks practical benefit.
  2. Kent Greenwall: so much debate over whether duress or mistaken self-defence is a justification or excuse which shows the distinction is too vague to be useful.
  3. Some commentators argue that our society lacks agreed moral standards which can be used to assess the justifiability or not of particular actions. For the law to declare such actions justifiable or not is to impose a moral judgement when society lacks a sufficient consensus on the issue.
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
19
Q

Character, choice and capacity

A

> Considering the theoretical foundations of defences can be complementary to or independent from analysing them in terms of justifications or excuses.
3 main schools of thought: choice theory, capacity theory and character theory.
But within each there’s a diversity of opinions.
Some, e.g. Horder, think best not to have one overarching theory of culpability as different ones may be more appropriate for different kinds of defences

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
20
Q

The Choice Theory - brief summary

A

> D should be punished only for what s/he has chosen to do.

>Supporters for this view tend to prefer subjective forms of MR, e.g. intention, Cunningham recklessness.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
21
Q

The Capacity Theory - brief summary

A

> Punishment is justified only for not only those who chose to commit the harm, but also those who could have avoided causing the harm but didn’t.
Defences apply when D did not and could not have chosen to obey the law.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
22
Q

The Character Theory - brief summary

A

> Argues that D’s criminal act reflects D’s bad character.

>A defence should exist when the act doesn’t reveal bad character.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
23
Q

Nicola Lacey, ‘Space, Time and Function: Intersecting Principles of Responsibility across the Terrain of Criminal Justice’ - ‘Capacity’ principles: choice & opportunity

A

> Foundation of this view is that not only a person’s status as a responsible agent answerable to the normative demands of the criminal law but also of an attribution of responsibility for specific actions lies in human capacities of cognition and volition powers of self-control.
Rise in subjectivism within this theory
If the basic moral intuition underlying the capacity theory is that it is only legitimate to hold people criminally responsible for things which they had the capacity to avoid doing, we can realise this intuition in one of two ways:
-We can do so through a subjective choice in the sense of intention, awareness, knowledge (Williams, 1983)
-Or we can ask - as Hart did - whether the D had a fair opportunity to conform his or her behaviour to the criminal law standards.
This second approach implicates not only subjective mental states but also ‘objective’ standards like negligence or the imposition of reasonableness constraints in the specification of defences.
Further pro of opportunity version of capacity responsibility is that it is less susceptible than the choice version to the truth of determinism, in that the evaluation can be relative to socially pervasive reactive attitudes.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
24
Q

Nicola Lacey, ‘Space, Time and Function: Intersecting Principles of Responsibility across the Terrain of Criminal Justice’ - ‘Character’ principles: overall character; expressed disposition towards the relevant criminal law norms

A

> Martin Wiener has argued that it is possible for character and capacity theories to be combined as character responsibility implies holding us accountable for things which we could not, or had no fair opportunity to, avoid.
Most radical of the 2 character principles = ‘overall-character principle’:
-Holds that the attribution of criminal responsibility is founded in a judgment that D’s conduct is evidence of a wrongful, bad, disapproved character trait.
-The criminal law, on this view, seeks to convict, label and stigmatise those of bad character of disposition.
-Criminal conduct is at root a symptom of the underlying rationale for conviction & punishment, namely bad or anti-social character.
-Raises questions over scope of evidence: broad character evidence like criminal record, lifestyle, employment history?
In its more cautious form, character-responsibility restricts itself to an evaluation of the specific conduct which forms the basis for the present allegation.
As Tadros puts it, “does D’s conduct qua moral agent display the sort of vice which calls for criminal law’s communicative role of expressing moral indignation to be invoked?”
This view would naturally locate an attribution of responsibility within a broader time frame than that implied by the capacity principles. For the context within which an agent has acted - a history of domestic abuse, for example - will be relevant to an evaluation of the disposition which that action expresses.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
25
Q

The Capacity Theory - what is it?

A

> Hart: “a person is not to be blamed for what he has done if he could not help doing it.”
Dressler: it is appropriate to punish only a person who is responsible for their actions.
Uniacke: lacked fair opportunity to choose to act otherwise.
Michael Moore argues that the emphasis the capacity theory places on the ability to be able to choose reflects the wider attitude in society that the ability to choose is an important freedom.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
26
Q

The Capacity Theory - problems with the capacity theory

A
  1. The consideration of whether D freely chose to commit the crime is too narrow. E.g. different socio-economic backgrounds means people don’t start on level playing field as regards the likelihood they will commit a crime. Court doesn’t take this into consideration.
  2. In focusing on choice, it doesn’t take into account a wide enough range of factors in assessing D’s blameworthiness.
    - Bennet, Reilly: other factors, e.g. emotions are irrelevant for capacity theory.
  3. John Gardner suggests the capacity theory is misleading.
    - E.g. in a duress case, asking whether D had the capacity to act more bravely is misconceived.
27
Q

The Character Theory - what is it?

A

> Assess criminal liability on the basis of the extent to which D’s actions have displayed good or bad character.
Glover: “[T]o blame a person for an action is more than merely to say that he has brought about something we object to. We disapprove, not merely of the action or its consequence, but of him.”
Mousourakis: Character theory enables law to undertake a sensitive assessment of Ds
‘s culpability.
Wider range of factors than simply element of choice (focus of capacity theory).

28
Q

The Character Theory - problems

A
  1. Character theory assumes people are responsible for their characters.
    - If disagree with that then theory loses its attractiveness (Vuoso).
    - M. Moore counter = responsible for our character as we choose kind of people we are.
    - Argument risks reducing character theory to version of choice theory.
  2. What about actions which are ‘out of character’?
    - One lapse in character.
    - Duff argues that such a person has shown a character flaw and that an honest person would always resist the temptation to be dishonest.
    - How can one act reveal a character through a single action?
    - Some character theorists, e.g. Bayle, suggest a person is only responsible for stable character traits whilst others, e.g. Horder, rejects such an argument.
  3. Brudner: why do we look only to criminal actions to decide whether or not D has exhibited a criminal trait?
    - Why do you need an offence to convict such person?
    - Antony Duff argues you can’t claim to have a certain characteristic unless you act in a way which reveals that character. However, D could be examined by psychiatrists and found to be predisposed to commit criminal acts, even though he is yet to commit any. Should not the character theory be willing to convict such a person because ‘we know’ he has a criminal character?
    - George Fletcher, in defending theory, says that an important principle of privacy comes into play to prevent conviction of a person with a criminally inclined character who has yet to act in a criminal way.
29
Q

Differences between the character & capacity theories

A

> Can overlap, e.g. D who lacks opportunity to comply with the law is not exhibiting bad character.
Where may disagree:

  1. D is overcome with anger & hatred and loses control and commits offence.
    - Character theorists: no defence because exhibits bad character.
    - Capacity theorists: harder, as can such a person claim they didn’t choose to act freely; or didn’t have fair opportunity to act otherwise given personality (e.g. particularly short-tempered)?
  2. D acts totally out of character on a one-off offence caused by say, his wife dying.
    - Capacity theorists: guilty.
    - Character theorists: in light of his previous exemplary behaviour & the unusual circumstances can we say his actions reflect a character trait? Is this conduct not just simply out-of-character? Temptation is to say that any chosen behaviour is ‘in character’ but this becomes very close to the choice theory.

> Some, e.g. Duff, argue there’s no effective different between the choice & character theories.
The Qs whether the choice was genuine & whether the choice was one which reflects badly on D’s character merge together?

30
Q

Determinism

A

> Determinism is the theory that all our actions are determined by factors outside our control.
Kelman, Norrie, Kenny: if determinism is correct, it produces problems for both the capacity & character theories and the blaming function of the criminal law.
If our actions are predetermined, how can we blame people for the ‘choices’ they make?
If our characters are a result of our genes to what extent can we hold people responsible for their characters?
Aristotle, Wolf, Dennett: even if our actions are to a large extent affected by genetic, social, environment, and other factors outside our control, we still have an element of control over our actions.
Key Q = accepting that to some extent our actions are affected by genetic, social, and economic factors, is the impact of those factors sufficient to justify providing a defence?
Dif. social backgrounds = different likelihood of committing an offence so some commentators, e.g. Delgado & Bazelon, argue for a defence of ‘rotten social background’.

31
Q

Insanity - problems with the present law - overview

A

> Mason & Mercer: Treatment & position of mentally disordered people = problematic for society in many areas, not just the criminal law.
Delicate balance between protecting interests of mentally disordered person, and the wider community’s interests.
Gunn and Taylor point out that the risk a mentally ill person will commit suicide is about 100 times greater than the risk of being killed by one.
A study by Norval Morris in 1982 found that a cohort of mentally disordered people with range of mental illnesses had no greater incidence of criminal offending than same-sized cohort of people randomly selected from the community and that in fact, males 14-22yrs from deprived inner-city areas had far higher incidence of offending behaviour than the mentally disordered group.

32
Q

Insanity - problems with the present law - difficulties in finding the appropriate response of criminal law to mental abnormalities

A
  1. Gross: did D commit crime because of mental illness or would they have committed anyway? But as Daniel Robinson says, this is a difficult Q to answer.
  2. Gostin, Gray, Laing, & Noaks: all too easy to merge the Qs whether D should be convicted of a criminal offence (‘public need protection from dangerous people’) and whether D should be detained in order to receive compulsory treatment (‘we need to offer treatment to those that are mentally ill’)?
    - Both pressurise the system to facilitate the detention of the mentally ill.
  3. Which definition?
    - Legal issue? Medical expertise?
    - D. Robinson: ‘ordinary meaning’ as understood by members of the public.
    - Morse suggests directing jury to consider where D was ‘crazy’.
    - Currently, legal definition of insanity is different from medical one so doctors giving evidence have difficulty of matching medical diagnoses with the legal terminology used.
  4. Why do the insane receive special treatment under the law?
    - No MR? Then just rely on defence of ‘no MR’?
    - Michael Moore: argue the criminal law is addressed to those who are rational and have the capacity to comply with its rules.
    - Slobogin: difficult to decide whether mentally ill person could have avoided breaking law.
33
Q

Insanity - Victor Tadros

A

> V. Tadros, Criminal Responsibility.
Objections to M’Naghten test for insanity:

  1. Rules are too broad as suggest any failure to appreciate the nature and quality of the act or that it was wrong will be sufficient to undermine responsibility.
    - Fails to recognise possibility that D is fully responsible for his cognitive & evaluative failure.
    - Should only be entitled to an excuse if D has made a cognitive or evaluative error which is radically detached from his background beliefs & values.
  2. Rules are too narrow:
    i) Doesn’t provide defence of those who lack autonomy to develop coherent & independent lives in general. Don’t have status-responsibility.
    ii) Rules don’t understand the significane of time for responsibilIty.
    - They fail to appreciate that there may be Ds who have undergone personality change such that the beliefs & desires that they have aren’t reflective of their settled character.
  3. Rules don’t include a volitional limb.
    - Fail to appreciate Ds whose desires are radically detached from their system of beliefs & values in such a way that does not reflect on them qua agent.
    - Should have a defence if those desires are sufficiently strong that an agent of good character is unable to resist them.

> M’Naghten Rules have 2 overly broad limbs where there ought to be 5 narrow limbs to mental disorder defences.

34
Q

Tadros - status responsibility

A

> To have what Tadros calls “status responsibility”, a threshold concept, an agent must be
“capable of forming true beliefs and evaluations about the world” and realising his or her beliefs
in action.
In this account, the process of assessing an agent’s status responsibility mustbe historicised because an agent’s identity persists over time.
For this reason, Tadros is critical of mental disorder defences, suggesting that they pay insufficient attention to “the effect of the mental disorder in relation to the agent as she persists over time”.
Once it has been determined that an agent has status responsibility, it is necessary to determine what the agent did.
For Tadros, questions of causation are “intimately related” to responsibility.
He goes on to argue that the principles of causation are social (or normative) and natural.

35
Q

Insanity - reform of present law - overview

A

> Unacceptable to label epileptics, diabetics, sleepwalkers as insane against medical expertise.
Distinction between external & internal factors upon which the law’s approach places a great deal of weight, can produce arbitrary distinctions.
Very few Ds seek to rely on defence of insanity.
Law Commission says that the theoretical problems in practice of definition of insanity could be ‘worked around’ and caused few practical problems.
1. Abolish insanity defence.
2.

36
Q

Insanity - reform of present law - Abolishing the insanity defence

A

> Hogg.

  1. N. Morris; Slobogin: An insane D should be able to rely on exactly same defences as sane D.
    - Szasz: an insane person who lacks MR for a crime or has a defence, deserves to be acquitted like any other citizen.
    - Goldstein: could still be required to undergo compulsory treatment under civil law.
    - But under SL or negligence-based offences an insane person wouldn’t have a defence.
  2. Thomas Szasz: extreme view that mental illness is a fiction, a convenient myth created by the mentally ill & those who care from them.
    -Argues ‘mental illness’ is a form of survival mechanism which people use to cope with life.
    -Although few would support this nowadays, it is hard to deny his claim that the line between mental illness, eccentricity, and ‘normality’ is hard to draw.
    -Rosenhan: it isn’t difficult to find evidence of people classified as ‘insane’ who in fact shouldn’t have been.
    >Hill: concerning evidence that the rate of mental illness correlates strongly with social & economic circumstances.
37
Q

Insanity - reform of present law - Law Commission are considering reform on the law of insanity

A

> Law Commission, Criminal Liability: Insanity & Automatism - A Discussion Paper (2013):

  1. We provisionally propose the creation of a new statutory defence of not criminally responsible by reason of recognised medical condition.
  2. Party seeking to raise the new defence must adduce expert evidence that D wholly lacked the capacity:
    i) to rationally form a judgment about the relevant conduct or circumstances;
    ii) to understand the wrongfulness of what they are charged with having done; or
    iii) to control their acts in relation to the relevant conduct or circumstances as a result of a qualifying recognised medical condition.
  3. We provisionally propose certain conditions wouldn’t qualify.
    - These include acute intoxication or any condition which is manifested solely or principally by abnormally aggressive or seriously irresponsible behaviour.
38
Q

Private Defence - The Moral Basis of Private Defence - Why should the criminal law provide a defence to those who use force in order to protect themselves or others?

A
  1. Consequentialist Theory
  2. The Forfeiture Theory
  3. Autonomy Arguments for Self-Defence
39
Q

Private Defence - The Moral Basis of Private Defence - Why should the criminal law provide a defence to those who use force in order to protect themselves or others? THE CONSEQUENTIALIST THEORY

A

> Where force is used in self-defence better consequences are produced than where it’s not.
Sangero argues that it is better the aggressor is harmed than the person being attacked because the aggressor devalues his interests by the attack.
Contravenes the normal principle that all lives are equally valuable.
Leverick: causes problems where person being attacked has behaved badly too.
Sangero also argues that the maintenance of the ‘rule of law and order’ justifies giving greater weight to person being attacked.
Although whether the existence of the defence discourages attacks & helps maintain order is open to question.
Argument woulnd’t support use of self-defence where D thought was being attacked but aren’t.
How much more than proportional retaliation justified better consequence?

40
Q

Private Defence - The Moral Basis of Private Defence - Why should the criminal law provide a defence to those who use force in order to protect themselves or others? THE FORFEITURE THEORY

A

> Hugo Bedau: “[The wrongdoer] no longer merits our consideration, any more than an insect or a stone does.”
Forfeit right not to have violence used against them.
Suzanne Uniacke: a person’s right to life or freedom from violence is conditional upon that person not posing a threat to other people. When posing a threat the person doesn’t have those rights.
Criticisms:

  1. How does this explain that once threat ceases V can’t be attacked?
    - Uniacke claims once threat no longer posed, V reacquires right to life.
    - Still leaves an ambiguous point in time.
  2. How can you say a child or insane person forfeits their right by posing a threat?
    - Controversial response = a right can be forfeited by your actions even if you aren’t morally responsible for them.
    - Others accept forfeiture theory has no application where the attackers are innocent.
    - Difficult to justify killing apart from referring to a right to defend yourself or a theory of forfeiture.
  3. How does the FT explain the proportionality requirement?
    - Do you lose/forfeit all rights?
    - Supporters may reply that on posing a threat to another the attacker loses the right not to have force proportionate to the threatened force used against them.
  4. If V tries to kill D and V thereby forfeits right to life, can D kill V in a particular brutal way?
    - Most say D must kill in least painful way, but under the forfeiture theory V has lost his right to life and so D can choose.
41
Q

Private Defence - The Moral Basis of Private Defence - Why should the criminal law provide a defence to those who use force in order to protect themselves or others? AUTONOMY ARGUMENTS FOR SELF-DEFENCE

A

> D has right to defend him/herself.
Dressler: responsibility of state to protect its citizens from violence & if the state is unable to protect the citizen (because there’s an imminent attack) then the citizen is able to intervene & use force.
Rights of autonomy.
Nourse distinguishes between what she calls the pacifist position, with its focus on the right to life of V and stressing requirements or proportionality and necessity, and the libertarian view, which focuses on D’s right of autonomy.
Wallerstein: doesn’t make it clear why self-defence is available only in face of an unjust threat?

42
Q

Private Defence - The Moral Basis of Private Defence - Why should the criminal law provide a defence to those who use force in order to protect themselves or others? Trolley Problem

A

> Victor Tadros:
-“It is wrong to kill one person to save 5 if the one person is used as a means, but not if the death of the one is a side effect of the good-producing action.”

43
Q

Mistaken Private Defence

A

> Can rely on private defence despite mistake.
In Beckford, court focused on HoL decision in Morgan that unlawfulness is an element of all crimes of violence. As the MR of a crime must relate to all aspects of the AR the D must intend or be reckless as to the unlawfulness.
Therefore, if the person believes the state of affairs to be such that they would have a defence to any criminal charge they lack the intent or recklessness as to the unlawfulness part of the AR.
Frowe: not practical to require people to know if they are being attacked.

44
Q

Private Defence - The ‘Householder’ Provisions

A

> S. 43 of Crime and Courts Act 2013 has introduced special provisions to deal with householders pleading self-defence after using violence against intruders.
Dsouza justifies the provision on basis D has special entitlement to stay in their home.
Nicola Wake critcises these reforms:
-Revised test has potential to raise the bar dangerously in terms of the amount of force which can legitimately be used in ‘startled householder’ cases.
-Determining the point at which force is to be regarded as grossly disproportionate is as decipherable as assessment of how many angels can dance on the head of a pin.
-It is disturbing that the gov. asserts that the line is crossed when it is abundantly clear that no further force is required.
-Perplexed jurors will be required to engage in mental gymnastics in order to determine whether D’s conduct is to be regarded as reasonable, disproportionate, or grossly disproportionate.
-New provision is dangerous in terms of the level of violence it permits.
-Enigmatic.
-Grayling (a gov. minister) asserts that “being confronted by an intruder in your own home is terrifying, and the public should be in no doubt that the law is on their side.”
-Can’t be convincingly reconciled with cases involving prolonged and systematic violent domestic abuse suffered in the familial home.
-The ‘abused woman’ who kills using disproportionate force in the home doesn’t benefit from this change in the law because the person who attacks her isn’t a stranger.

45
Q

Duress - the debate over the proper basis

A
  1. The ‘no choice’ model.
  2. The ‘lack of choice’ model.
  3. The ‘character’ model.
  4. Justification.
  5. The ‘no mens rea’ model.
    >Herring: It is quite possible that more than one of these theories is correct.
    >Duff, supporting the character theory, suggests that ‘we should ascribe to the reasonable person any of D’s actual characteristics that affected her response to the threat, other than characteristics which involve either some lack of reasonable regard for the law and its values, or a lack of reasonable courage.’
46
Q

Duress - the ‘no choice’ model

A

> Threat causes such panic, they are incapable of rational thought.
Almost like a ‘temporary insanity’ although Lord Wilberforce rejected the use of such terminology in DPP for NI v Lynch [1975].
Opponents, e.g. Morse, argue the law must consider whether D ought to have found this such a difficult choice.

47
Q

Duress - the ‘lack of choice’ model

A

> M. Moore: even though D may have been able to consider options before choosing to commit a crime, they shouldn’t be responsible for their choice.
Moore: as capacity theory would have it, they didn’t have a fair opportunity to choose to otherwise.

48
Q

Duress - the ‘character’ model

A

> Richards: When acting under duress, D’s behaviour doesn’t reveal a bad character.
Focuses on appropriateness of choice D made.
D may have made the morally correct choice or was it the wrong choice, but bearing in mind that even morally well-disposed agents are affected by panic & fear, it’s one such an agent might have made and doesn’t reflect bad character (Horder, Alexander).

49
Q

Duress - justification

A

> Wertheimer, Honore, J. Gardner: D made a morally permissible choice.
Wertheimer: choice need only be permissible so D will be justified if harm required to commit it is same as or less than harm threatened.
Ferzan: does justification require the act to be permissible or morally right?

50
Q

Duress - ‘no MR’ model

A

> D didn’t intend to harm V, but rather the purpose was to avoid the threat being carried out.

51
Q

K. Kessler Ferzan, ‘Justification and Excuse’

A
  1. Choice, Reasoning, and Attitude:
    - “Choice theorists argue that the grounds for excusing an actor are that she lacked the rationality to appreciate the criminality of her conduct or the volitional ability to conform her conduct to the requirements of law.
    - “It is overinclusive, as it would arguably excuse the negligent who do not make choices.”
    - “Michael Moore has argued that there is different culpability at work for negligence - the culpability of unexercised capacity.”
  2. Character Theories
    - “Underlying this theory is the view that one is ultimately responsible for one’s character, and actions are just proxies for character.”
    - “Seems that even if an action is ‘out of character’ that should not be sufficient to exculpate a D.”
    - Suggests that “the commission of a criminal act is merely evidentiary as opposed to providing the primary basis for responsibility.” This view is “utterly at odds with evidence law, which prohibits the use of character evidence to show that an action was or was not in conformity with the actor’s character.”
    - “Character theorists seem to get the relationship between character and action exactly backward - action is prior to, and constitutive of, character. To put the the matter bluntly, one act of theft makes you a thief.”
  3. Reasons and Excuses
    - “Excuses look to the actor’s reasons that thereby reveal him not to be blameworthy for the act. Notably, various theorists offer quite disparate views of how these reasons are said to undermine blameworthiness. 3 leading views are set forth below:”
    - Gardner’s view is that the gist of excuses is living up to societal expectations.
    - Like Gardner, Horder distinguishes excuses in terms of reasons for denials of responsibility, which fall within the categories oof exemptions, although Horder does make room for a partial excuse of diminished responsibility. His general view is that excuses place D’s act in a more favourable light, when the ‘morally active’ reasons for his conduct are scrutinised. Actor’s reasons reflect on the act not simply the actor.
52
Q

Necessity

A

> Present law recognises that necessity is available where the offence is committed which promotes the well-being of a ‘victim’ who is unable to consent.
The reluctance of the English law to accept a general ‘lesser of two evils’ necessity defence at first sight seems hard to justify, but as Simon Gardner explores, there are not just practical difficulties with such a defence, but also theoretical & political ones.
Peter Glazebrook has argued it is unjustifiable to support the lesser of two evils in circumstances of duress or self-defence, but not in other circumstances.
Alan Norrie picks up on this argument and points out that the existing defences are provided for the kinds of cases in which the more powerful people may find themselves but not in the circumstances in which marginalised members or society are likely to find themselves (e.g. intending to steal food to escape hunger.

53
Q

Necessity - S. Gardner, ‘Direct Action and the Defence of Necessity’

A

> Utilitarian assessment of the competing goods and harms.
Ethically impossible exercise.
Consider Re A (Children) (Conjoined Twins: Surgical Separation): rejecting the medico-economic arguments adduced by Ward L.J., many would regard the question as unanswerable, and not the less so for being addressed by judges.
We cannot expect judges to answer a question like that, and it would do no more than brush the difficulty under the carpet to leave it to be decided by the jury.
A utilitarian assessment does look more possible where human life and limb, or the interests of the state, are not at stake: say in looking at monetary value of objects broken but to take a utilitarian approach even here is to disregard the value which I, and especially you, may subjectively attach to our property.
It is much more comfortable to think of necessity in terms of the vindication of rights.
It’s superior to any right or interest that the offence exists to protect.

54
Q

The rights theory of necessity

A

> Horder says that even if this inequality is accepted as unjust, the solution lies, not in allowing poor people to steal from rich, but rather through reforming the taxation and social security systems,
Horder, however, does recognise that there are some situations where political alternatives aren’t available.
This kind of emergency is not one to which Parliament is expected to find a solution.
Starving thief scenario gives rise to a number of Qs:
-How starving do you have to be to be able to steal and how rich does a person have to be for it to be permissible to steal from him?
Q of constitutional law: in recognising necessity, are the courts essentially making law by in effect creating a new exception to crime.
Thoburn argues that in recognising necessity the courts are reviewing the validity of the decision not to comply with the law, rather than changing the law itself.

55
Q

J. Herring, ‘Escaping the Shackles of Law at the End of Life’

A

> In considering Nicklinson v Ministry of Justice [2013], Herring makes a case in favour of allowing necessity in exceptional cases involving terminally ill people who wish to be killed.
The Samaritans suggest around 5% of the population will attempt suicide at some point in their life.
When considering how the law should respond to people who wish to die, we should remember that few suicides or attempted suicides are motivated by the kind of careful, calm, rational thinking expressed by, for example, Tony Nicklinson.
Suicide prevention is at the heart of the public health response to this issue. It should be at the heart of the legal response too.
Difficulty is that the law has its general principles, but then hard cases come along.
Create ‘wriggle room’ through prosecutorial discretion; the common sense of juries; providing minimal sentences; and the defence of necessity.
This is because human life is complex. It does not fit into clear boxes. A few statutory lines cannot in their nature produce the full assessment of blame or capture all the nuances of morally complex scenarios.
There is no breach of constitutional principle if the courts use these devices to ensure there’s no conviction in the rare case where the official response is inappropriate. Indeed, Parliament relies on these to make the criminal law workable. These devices are essential in an effective criminal law system. They are an acknowledgement of the limitations of language and an inability to deal in rules with all the minutiae of an individual case that are needed for an effective moral assessment. Without such devices, the individual defendant can bear the burden of the inevitably blunt nature of the law.
I believe utilising the defence of necessity would have provided the ideal response of the law to the issues raised.
We can acknowledge that in rare cases, compassion is met by not prosecuting or by using a defence of necessity.

56
Q

Issues which fall between the gaps of defences

A

> 3 controversial scenarios that don’t neatly fall into any of the established defences:

  1. Kingston [1994].
  2. Battered women.
  3. The Zeebrugge disaster.
57
Q

Issues which fall between the gaps of defences - Kingston

A

> HoL held that the D who was involuntarily intoxicated could still be convicted of an offence providing he has the necessary MR.
G.R. Sullivan, ‘Making Excuses’:
-If we take Hart’s classic epitome of excusing conditions and ask whether Kingston lacked fair opportunity and capacity to conform his conduct to law, we arguably affirm, not refute, the decision of the HoL.
-Although self-restraint was made more difficult for D, he seemingly remained in possession of sufficient volitional and cognitive resources with which to conform his conduct to law.
-A claim that one would not have indulged in drink or drugs is inherently plausible. Moreover, Lord Taylor, in giving judgment for the CA, remarked that involuntary intoxication should be a defence for all crimes of specific or basic intent.
-Under the Model Penal Code, involuntary intoxication will found a defence to any crime if it deprived D of ‘substantial capacity to conform his conduct to law.’
-If such a condition arose blamelessly and induced conduct which would not otherwise have occurred, this will attenuate to some extent the culpability of the agent.
-It has been suggested that his blameless state of disequilibrium must count in his favour, even if only as mitigation.
-Should mitigation be upgraded to excuse if, until this particular occasion, D had refrained from paedophiliac practices?
-Lord Mustill: a conviction for a serious offence needn’t entail descriptively or prescriptively that D was in any sense at fault.
-Should sanctions not be confined to the blameworthy?

58
Q

Issues which fall between the gaps of defences - Battered women

A

> What defence, if any, should be available to a woman who kills her sleeping partner following months of violence from him?

  1. Loss of control. Herring: difficulties arise in proving that there was loss of self-control, it was ‘sudden & temporary’, and D’s response was reasonable.
  2. Diminished responsibility. Suffering abnormality of mind (e.g. BWS although some commentators, like Loveless, are sceptical about its existence). Only available to charge of murder.
  3. Duress. Dressler, the leading proponent of this view, suggests the Q the law should ask is whether in face of threats of violence D acted in a reasonable way. Horder argues duress is inappropriate as there’s no threat which D is giving in to.
  4. Self-defence. Difficult as she needs to satisfy ‘requirement’ she was attacking herself from an imminent attack (although Horder argues there is no requirement of imminence as such and it is simply a Q of whether D was acting reasonably). Dressler: could be argues she had opportunity to escape from prospective attack by leaving home and therefore use of violence wasn’t necessary.
59
Q

Issues which fall between the gaps of defences - Battered women - A. McColgan, ‘General Defences’.

A

> Considers difficulties battered women face when seeking to use self-defence or other defences.
In those cases in which women kill when in fear for their lives, I argue that self-defence/justifiable force is more appropriate than either provocation or diminished responsibility.
Many women who kill abusive partners fulfil the ‘necessity’ requirement of self-defence (of which imminence is a factor). Some would do so on a purely objective test. Others kill in less apparently clear cut circumstances of which, particularly where the woman is not actually being assaulted at the time, some explanation might be required of why she needed to use force.
Even if a woman’s perception of the impossibility or futility of escape was adjudged inaccurate, the proper question is what she perceived, rather than whether that perception was reasonable. Where there was any significant doubt about the accuracy of such perception, evidence of BWS could be employed if relevant to support the woman’s claim that she regarded escape as impossible.
Proportionality: any assumption that an armed defence is disproportionate to an unarmed attack overlooks the fact that men are typically much stronger than the women they abuse.
Q of proportionality, like that of necessity, is an objective one. D must however be judged on the facts as she believed them to be.
Domestic violence typically follows a pattern of escalation.

60
Q

Distinction between duress & self-defence

A

> Is it easy to distinguish between a case of duress and a case of self-defence?
The law is said by some to be based on the principle that it cannot be justifiable to take an innocent person’s life.
Duress is defence to murder; self-defence is not as in duress, D was blameless but in self-defence, D was not.
Can a clear line be drawn between cases where V is or isn’t posing an unjust threat to D?

61
Q

F. Leverick, ‘Killing in Self-Defence’ - distinguishing necessity & self-defence

A

> Defining feature of a claim of self-defence is that it involves defensive force being directed towards the source of the threat posed.
Like self-defence, the defence of necessity can involve the infliction of harm on person, but unlike self-defence, this would involve harming a bystander who was not posing a direct threat.
That is not to say that the distinction between self-defence and necessity is always a clear one. There lie difficult cases at the borderline between the 2 defences, especially where passive threats are concerned.
Re A (Children): Ward LJ, identified the appropriate defence as self-defence, whereas another, Brooke LJ, analysed the case in terms of necessity.
-Uniacke has doubted that the case is one of self-defence on the basis that for Mary to be a direct threat to Jodie, there needs to be some prior position of Jodie’s that Mary directly threatened.

62
Q

F. Leverick, ‘Killing in Self-Defence’ - distinguishing self-defence from duress

A

> Distinction lies in the nature of the act undertaken by the accused.
In a case of self-defence, the accused avoids harm by warding off or blocking a threat whereas, in a case of duress, the accused avoids harm by complying with the demands of the threatener.
This relatively clear-cut distinction hasn’t stopped some from confusing acts of self-defence with acts committed under duress.
Sometimes suggested that a further distinction can be made between self-defence & duress, based on V’s status.
That is in cases of self-defence, the accused harms someone who was a direct threat to her life or bodily integrity, whereas in cases of duress, the accused harms an innocent V who isn’t the source of the threat.
Although it is possible to envisage a scenario where the person issuing the threats demands that the accused harms not an innocent V, but the threatener herself.

63
Q

F. Leverick, ‘Killing in Self-Defence’ - A unified defences of ‘necessary action’?

A

> Clarkson argues that the defences of self-defence, necessity and duress should be brought together under a unified defence (termed ‘necessary action’) governed by the same rules.
For Clarkson “what unites these actions is more important than what separates them. In all of them a D is committing a prima facie wrong in order to avoid some sort of crisis. To protect herself and/or other persons the D is committing what would otherwise be a crime and the true issue is how the law should respond to these actions and in what circumstances it should afford a defence.”
While it is true that the defences have much in common, there is nonetheless something to be said for treating necessity, duress, and self-defence as distinct defences.
Public policy issues relating to each aren’t identical.
E.g. there’s an argument for placing more stringent restrictions on duress than on the other 2 defences because of the risk that the defence is abused by terrorist groups or other criminal organisations. Indeed, this was precisely the reason given by the HoL in R v Hasan for imposing stricter conditions on the defence of duress (where D is judged according to an objective test) than on the defence of self-defence (where a subjective test is applied).
Also argument made for conceptual separation of the 3 defences on the grounds of fair labelling.
Needs right defence as she may be morally judged by society on basis of the label.
Self-defence reflects more favourably on the accused than duress?