Deontology Flashcards

1
Q

Give a fact to illustrate the influence K has had on philosophy

A

K’s influence is so great that philosophy is sometimes divided into pre and post K

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
2
Q

What did K think humans could do?

A

Central to his project was the idea that humans could use their reason to make the world a better place

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
3
Q

What cultural movement at the time did such an idea align with?

A

Such idealism was rge hallmark of the European Enlightenment (mid 17th century to the end of the 18th). Saw intellectuals increasingly turning to their own rationality, rather than religious doctrine, to solve the problems of the day. The era saw increased faith in the potential of the natural sciences and is often considered to be the intellectual birthplace of Western democracy: it was against the backdrop of the Enlightenment that the French and Americans Revolutions wrestled control from ancient monarchies and put in place their fledgling republicans

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
4
Q

What set K apart from other enlightenment thinkers?

A

What set K apart from other E figures was he commitment to finding out what reason could and could not tell us

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
5
Q

What did he famously talk of doing within philosophy?

A

He famously talked of instituting a copernican revolution in the way philosophy was done

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
6
Q

Explain the influence of religion on the way K wrote

A

K was a devout Christian, but largely tried to work from an agnostic basis. K thought we can’t know for sure whether God exists. He thought that we might have good reasons to believe in him, but we can not be absolutely certain that he exists. As a result, when he did write about God, he concentrated on how little we could know about him through speculative thought. This is why he criticised many of the arguments for the existence of God we have encountered

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
7
Q

What did he think we needed to do to discover the right thing to do in an ethical situation?

A

He thought that when it came to ethics, he thought that we need only to reflect to know what to do

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
8
Q

Give a quote from K to display his idea that moral law is within us

A

‘Two things fill the mind with ever new and increasing admiration and awe, the more often we steadily reflect on them: the starry heavens above me and the moral law within me’

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
9
Q

Explain K’s idea that reason governs morality

A

K thinks reason governs morality. Knowing what is right and wrong is like solving an equation: there is only one correct answer, and we simply apply the right method to find it

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
10
Q

Explain the link K makes between acting morally and the fact that we are rational beings

A

Doing the right thing is our duty as rational beings. If we do the wrong thing we are not just acting immorally, but irrationally too

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
11
Q

What two types of imperitives does he distinguish between?

A

Hypothetical and categorical

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
12
Q

What are imperitives?

A

Imperatives are just commands – instructions which tell is what to do

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
13
Q

What are hypothetical imperitives?

A

Hypothetical imperatives usually look like this: ‘You ought to do X if you want to get Y’. They command us to do something if we want something else. They are conditional commands.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
14
Q

What are categorical imperatives?

A

Categorical imperatives are usually in the form ‘You ought to do X’. They command us to just do it. They are unconditional commands

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
15
Q

What does K see as the only way of performing a good action?

A

K thinks we can only do something good if it is done unconditionally, with no strings attached. As a result, it is our duty to do good. For instance, it is a soldier’s duty to protect the nation, so even if they wake up that morning and don’t feel like fighting, they still must do it

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
16
Q

Give a quote that illustrates K’s idea that only intentions matter

A

‘Nothing in the world, or out of it, can possibly be conceived that could be called ‘good’ without qualification except a ‘good will’. It isn’t what brings it about, its usefulness in achieving some intended end. Rather, good will is good because of how it wills, it is good in itself

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
17
Q

Explain K’s idea that it is the intention behind actions that matters

A

He goes on to say that other things which might be considered good, such as ‘intelligence, wit and judgement’ and crucially happiness, if misused or misappropriated, can be bad. This good will is said to ‘sparkle like a jewel all by itself’; its value doesn’t ‘go up or down depending on how useful or fruitless it is’. It is ‘the condition of all other goods, even the desire for happiness’; it is life lived in accordance with reason

It doesn’t make sense to say anything else is good, because rationality requires a good that is absolute – whereas, any other thing we might consider to be good, could, in some circumstances, turn out to be bad. From this standpoint, K derives his entire system of deontological ethics

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
18
Q

Give a quote from K where he explains the first formulation

A

‘Act only in accordance with that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it become a universal law’ (Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals)

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
19
Q

What does the first formulation mean we must do when faced with an ethical decision?

A

K’s first form of the categorical imperative gives rise to a particular procedure for making moral decisions which is sometimes known as the universalisability test. The core idea is that when we make any moral decision, we must ask ourselves whether everybody else could do the same thing in similar circumstances. In K’s language, we are making a maxim and working out whether it could become a universal law

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
20
Q

Give an example of a proposition that is not universalisable

A

For some actions, this is clearly impossible. For example, if someone came up with the universal maxim that it is permissible to steal whenever you like, this would become self-defeating, as constant stealing would erode the notion of private property altogether, thus meaning that there would be nothing to steal

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
21
Q

Give an example of a proposition that is easily universalisable

A

On the other hand, the maxim, ‘it is permissible to torture small children’, can easily be univeralised. If nobody ever tortures small children, no problem is likely to arise. There is nothing contradictory or self-defeating about this rule. However, the opposite maxim, that torturing small children is okay, could quickly lead to problems

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
22
Q

What is another reason why K would disagree with torture?

A

K would also have a problem with torture because it treats people as a means to an end

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
23
Q

What two categories does K divide duties into?

A

In Groundwork, K divides duties into the categories of perfect and imperfect

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
24
Q

What are perfect duties?

A

Perfect duties are those such as ‘do not kill’ or ‘do not steal’ - their universalisation involves an obvious logical contradiction (logical contradictions)

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
25
Q

Explain the idea of imperfect duties

A

Imperfect duties are those that don’t involve an obvious logical contradiction but are nonetheless undesirable for a rational being. For instance, there is no logical contradiction in univeralising the maxim, ‘when in need, feel free to urinate on tombstones’; as society would not collapse if people did this. However, this does change the fact that it is hard to imagine a society where people are happy defiling the resting places of their ancestors . K would therefore argue we have an imperfect duty not to act disrespectfully towards the dead (contradiction of the will)

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
26
Q

State the second formulation

A

‘So act as to treat humanity, both in your own person, and in the person of every other, always as the same time as an end, never simply as a means’

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
27
Q

Explain how utilitarianism fails as far as the second formulation is concerned

A

One of the problems we encountered with utilitarianism was its dubious stance on human rights. As a relativist theory, all options are on the table. For instance, torturing an innocent would be permissible if it did something like saving lots of lives

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
28
Q

What is K’s response to this problem and what has it been called?

A

K takes the opposite view – certain actions are never permissible. It is this aspect of his philosophy, the so called ‘Humanity Formula’, which has the most enduring influence on western thought

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
29
Q

What is the crucial idea behind the second formulation?

A

The crucial idea here is that people can never be used as a means to an end

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
30
Q

How does this have a practical appeal?

A

There is an intuitive appeal to this idea. This is something deeply unsettling about the idea of someone doing things with or to you, not because they like or value you, but for some other purpose. K recognised this and thought he could explain why we feel negative about things like this. He thinks people feel like this because they are rational beings, and rational beings deserve dignity and respect, and this involves always treating them as an end in and of themselves

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
31
Q

Explain the third formulation

A

‘Act according to the maxims of a member of a merely possible kingdom of ends, legislating in it universally’. This is known as ‘The Kingdom of Ends Formula’; it refers to how we should treat one another in an ideal moral society

For his final formulation of the categorical imperative. K envisions a utopian Kingdom of Ends where all people share the same moral vision, desiring the same goods and sharing the same ends. It build upon the two previous formulations, as the laws the hypothetical members of the kingdom would devise are based on the ‘universal law of nature’ and ‘humanity’ formulas

Hence any moral laws made would be universalisable without contradiction and treat people as ends

This third formulation adds a political component to the theory: he is trying to tell us how society would be governed if people were willing to accept his deontological ethics. Therefore when acting individually, we should imagine whether are action would be acceptable in the hypothetical kingdom in the hope that by doing so, we might bring it closer to becoming a reality

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
32
Q

Name another philosopher that promoted deontological ethics

A

WD Ross

33
Q

Explain his theory

A

He argued that in ethical situations, all moral agents have a certain type of duty – prima facie duties. This is a Latin phrase which means ‘at first appearance’ or prior to closer inspection. They are duties we can instantly recognise and which become apparent through our intuition. However, further consideration is needed to know exactly how to act upon them or apply them in an ethical situation. We need to make our own judgements about how to act upon our duties

Ross identified 7 prima facie duties…

34
Q

List these 7 prima facie duties

A

Promise keeping

Reparation

Gratitude

Justice

Beneficence

Self improvement

Non malificence (avoiding actions that do harm)

35
Q

When does Ross think our duty becomes apparent?

A

Ross said that before the ethical situation arises, we cannot know what our duty is. Our duties become apparent in the situation and we will be able to recognise what we should do

36
Q

What does he say we should do if two duties come into conflict?

A

If two duties come into conflict, niether should be ignored, but the moral agent should determine which is more important

37
Q

List the weaknesses of his theory

A

There is insignificant acknowledgement of the importance of rights because it leaves what is one’s duty open to subjective interpretation, rather than recognising there are objective rights in certain situations

Today, many people follow individualism and reject the notion of duties

38
Q

List the strengths of Ross theory

A

More flexible that K’s theory and allows for a more subjective interpretation of what duties are important in different situations or time periods. This allows for greater flexibility and consideration of consequences. For instance, the duty to tell the truth to a murderer about the whearabouts of your friend becomes less important than the duty to protect your friend. Ross’ theory therefore finds a middle ground between consequentialism and absolute deonotology

It allows for partial favouring of friends and family by recognising your duty towards them. This makes it more practical than impartial ethical theories that require impartial ethical treatment

39
Q

What did Thomas Nagel develop?

A

Developed an influential account of deontology that built upon K

40
Q

What two types of reasons for moral action does he distinguish between?

A

Distinguishes between agent relative and agent neutral reasons for moral action

41
Q

What are agent relative reasons?

A

Agent relative reasons are reasons for someone to do or not do something that is a reason just for them, not others.

42
Q

What are agent neutral reasons?

A

Agent neutral reasons are general reasons for anyone to do or not do something; these reasons apply to everyone

43
Q

What type of reason does Nagel think utilitarian theories offer and why?

A

Nagel argues that utilitarian theories offer agent neutral reasons for actions. The essence of utilitarian thought is to assume objectivity, it is not my pleasure that counts, but the greatest pleasure for the greatest number

44
Q

How does Nagel think that deontological theories differ here?

A

Nagel believes deontological theories provide agent relative reasons, justifying our proclivity to act differently towards friends and family

45
Q

What have both utilitarian and deontological theories been criticised for in terms of their practicality?

A

Both U and D theories have often been criticised for demanding too much of people

46
Q

How does Bernard Williams illustrate this idea?

A

Bernard Williams asks us to imagine a situation where a man can only save one of two people from a shipwreck. One of them is his wife who he loves, the other is a complete stranger. The man will almost definitely save his wife. For both deontology and utilitarianism, the moral justification for this relatively simple decision is going to be complex. From a purely impartial perspective, we have no reason to choose the person we love over the person we don’t. We must instead consider factors such as ‘how much pleasure will their survival bring’ or ‘whether I can legislate a universal maxim’. Williams calls this ‘having one thought too many’; for the man to save his wife is surely a moral no brainer, but both theories seem to demand rather arcane justifications

47
Q

How does Nagel’s theory manage to avoid this issue?

A

Nagel sidesteps this difficulty because he holds that deontology actually requires that there be obligations for some people that do not apply to others. This captures the intensely personal process of ethical decision making and also avoids some of the issues with K’s deontology

48
Q

How does this theory still manage to be deontological despite offering this sense of relativity?

A

Crucially, agent relative reasons are not grounded in our subjective emotions but in the claims of others on us. For instance, parents have a duty to look after their children, not because they feel that they must, but because children have a claim on their parents, and only their parents, to look after them. These claims are still deontological because they are absoluet duties; however, we are able to dispense with the Kantian notion that we must always be legislating as if in an ideal moral universe

49
Q

How does Nagel avoid the impracticality of the third formulation?

A

Nagel accepts that this kind of universe does not exist, and that our first and foremost responsibility is to carry out those duties that apply to us

50
Q

How does Kantian ethics view the treatment of animals?

A

Since animals are not rational beings there is no requirement not to treat them as a means to an end. K even remarks that there is nothing wrong with torturing an animal, but caveats that such behaviouir would lead a harshness of character…

51
Q

Give a quote from K that summarises this view

A

‘If a man shoots his dog because the animal is no longer capable of service, he does not fail in his duty to the dog, for the dog cannot judge, but the act is inhuman and damages in himself that humanity which it is his duty to show towards mankind. If he is not to stifle his human feelings, he must practise kindness towards animals, for he who is cruel to animals becomes hard also in his dealings with men (Kant, Lectures on Ethics, 212)

52
Q

Summarise the Kantian view on animals

A

In short, the traditional Kantian perspective disregards animals altogether, they are simply not a feature of the moral landscape

53
Q

How have contemporary deontologists challenged this viewpoint?

A

However, modern deontological perspectives attempt to promote animal welfare with a rights based account. Contemporary philosopher Tom Regan is particularly associated with this approach, arguing that animals have an inalienable right to life, just as humans do. As such, using animals for experimentation or food is a violation of this right. It is to use them as a means to an end and is therefore morally wrong. Crucially, Regan’s conception of inherent worth is not based on capacity for reason but on being the ‘subject of a life’, in other words, being that has a life of its own

54
Q

What did K think of war?

A

K ultimately sought universal peace, a programme he set out in a 1795 essay titled ‘Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch’. War involves killing, which is always wrong (as it contravenes both the first and second formulations of the categorical imperitive). However, he was aware that the political reality meant that wars sometimes take place and when they do, they needed to be carried out according to deontological rather than consequentialist principles. K supported the right for a nation to defend itself. This puts him squarely in line with the just war theory, although purely consequentialist principles like the likelihood of success would not figure in a deontological account of the justice of war

55
Q

List the strengths of deontological ethics

A

It is impossible to predict the consequences of our actions. It therefore seems more just to judge someone according to what they have control over, which is itself good or bad

It treats everyone equal and justly, which is line with the modern day idea of the rule of law

Creates core, absolute moral principles which cannot be dismissed because of changing societal concerns

Simplifies moral decision making because what is right and wrong is made clear

The categorical imperative creates rules consistent with what many people follow today, like the ideas that theft and murder are wrong. This makes it appear relevant and practical

Following our duty is more important than doing what we think is right, because this can be easily influences by our biases and selfish interests

Recognises the intrinsic value of humans. It protects them from being used for negative ends, as is the case in utilitarianism, where the minority could be made to suffer for the benefit of the majority

56
Q

Weaknesses

A

There seems to be little justification or authority for the moral obligations in deontological theories, unless one is willing to accept God as a divine lawgiver

It is not practical or possible to act according to duty alone, as human psychology and decision making are more complex than this

Following absolute moral commands or duty could result in awful consequences. There needs to be more flexibility to respond to complicated or extreme moral situations. Similarly, good consequences cannot be called actually good because what matters is the intention

It does not allow compassion or sympathy to motivate moral actions

K was a Christian and saw his ethic as consistent with Christianity, but God is sidelined. Vardy describes how ‘K largely reduced religion to ethics – to be holy is to be moral’. This may make the ethic less relevant to Christians

K’s principle of universalisation allows for the universalisation of amoral and immoral principles – just because a principle can be universalised, it does not mean it is right or sensible

Commits the naturalistic fallacy by falling victim to the is ought gap

There needs to be an actual reason to act according to ones duty – not simply because it is one’s duty

57
Q

Why would K disagree with the idea that we could lie about the whereabouts of a potential victim if questioned by a murderer?

A

The senisible thing to do here would be to deny that you know this, or even give him a false address. It seems like a terrible thing to actually tell the truth in this scenario. However, K would see this as the correct course of action as the maxim ‘lie whenever it suits you’ cannot be universalised, since if everyone followed this idea then very quickly we would all begin to no longer believe what everyone else says

58
Q

How does K respond to the case of the inquiring murderer?

A

A scenario similar to this was presented to K during his lifetime by one of his many critics. It has come to be known as ‘The Case of the Inquiring Murderer’. K’s own response to the problem is widely considered to be unsatisfactory. He suggests that in this scenario we should tell the truth because we cannot predict the consequences of not doing so. K says that giving a fake address could actually send the murderer to the woman’s secret hiding place. He says that in situations like these, it is therefore better in situations such as these to stick to the absolute rule because we will be held to account for disobeying it

59
Q

How does James Rachel counter this retort from K?

A

James Rachels, in ‘The Elements of Moral Philosophy’, points out two problems with this counter argument…

He asks if it really the case that our predictive powers are so limited. Predicting the future behaviour of other humans is essential to how society operates

Rachel points out that ‘Kant seems to assume that we would be morally responsible for any bad consequences of lying, but that we would not be similarly responsible for any bad consequences of telling the truth’. Either the consequences of what we do are morally relevant or they aren’t. K tries to have it both ways by suggesting that we will be held responsible for the negative consequences of our actions if we fail to follow our duty but not for these very same negative consequences if we do follow our duty

60
Q

What appears to be the obvious solution to this problem?

A

he obvious solution to this issue would be tio make the maxims we act upon more flexible. Instead of following the maxim ‘you ought not to lie’, why not say, ‘you ought not to lie unless doing so will save the persons life’. There is surely nothing self defeating about this maxim, and it would resolve the difficulties presented by this issue in a stroke

61
Q

What is the issue with this idea?

A

The trouble with this response is that it is unclear where to draw the line. It may be possible to make maxims so specific that any action becomes permissible, even ones that we would perhaps find objectionable

62
Q

Why did K therefore not make this arguement?

A

K likely foresaw the flaws in this kind of reasoning

63
Q

Why would it not have been reasonable for K to have made such a retort?

A

Crucial to his deontology ethics was the notion of consistency. If morality is to be binding, then it must apply to all people equally. We cannot have rules that work for one but not the other. As Rachel puts it, ‘if you accept any considerations as reasons in one case, you must also accept them as reasons in another cases’. One of the strengths of K’s position is that it ensures no one person is special or has interests which are of greater significance than anyone else

64
Q

What was Nietzsche say about K’s theory?

A

Nietszche would move from his view that all moral philosophy is culturally relative to claim that here we find a kind of morality that may have suited enlightenment Prussia, but which is irrelevant to the fractured world of today

65
Q

Counter this view

A

However, we could make the argument back that ethical theories should not be judged on their origin but on their merit. To argue otherwise is to commit the genetic fallacy, a type of arguementative mistake where an idea is discredited out of hand because of where it originated

66
Q

How do deontological ethics classify what makes an action good or bad

A

In relation to its commitment to a rule or set of rules. An act retains this good value even when it causes a bad consequence as long as it follows this framework. This makes ethics a separate field to that which is simply desirable. While the consequences of a moral action could still be something that it desired, but this is not what makes the act moral

67
Q

How does Kant classify what is moral

A

A duty that commands beyond something than just what the agent finds desirable. One’s duty can be defined as what they ought to do and Kant thinks that this ought can be discovered through reason

68
Q

Why can the categorical imperitive be seen as being based on reason

A

It is a rule that is separate from all contingent and hypothetical circumstances and can guide human ethical decision making irrespective on context

69
Q

Describe Kant’s distinction between phenomena and noumena and how this related to his ethics

A

Phenomena is the world we know through experience, while the noumena is the world in itself which we can think about but can not gain any knowledge of through experience.

Within the phenomena, causal determinism pertains as the world is governed by cause and effect

Kant speculates that the source of real free will that could give human moral actions significance is possibly contained within the noumena

70
Q

Why does Kant think that only rational beings are capable of being moral

A

If nature works in accordance with laws as Kant speculates, then only rational beings have the ability to understand these laws and act with this understanding in mind. What is ultimately behind this understanding is reason, and so the will is just reason engaged practically in the world

If reason is the mechanism that controls our actions, then what we do and will do in our lives is what are reason regards as necessary

71
Q

How does Kant acknowledge that reason is not the only thing guiding the will

A

He notes that humans are constantly under the pressure of their subjective conditions - outside influences based on the state of the world

72
Q

Why does Kant reject hypothetical imperatives

A

Because once the circumstances making it desirable are no longer there, the ‘ought’ loses its weight

With hypotheticals the statement cannot be known until the related conditions are known, whereas the categorical imperitive is known from the start and is universal

73
Q

Why does the categorical imperative have to be investigated a priori

A

Because it is not linked to aims or things that people regard as important, it cannot be grounded in a posteriori knowledge

74
Q

How does Kant arrive at the first formulation of the CI

A

The primary feature of a categorical imperitive is that it applies to anything in the universe, irrespective of that things being or state, what the imperitive commands is that a person’s actions can be repeated again across the entire universe. The action must be able to be performed at any time by anyone without logical contradiction or unintuitive results

75
Q

Why does the humanity formula give Kantian ethics such an appeal

A

Establishes the importance of respect between people and forms the idea of equality as an essential and rational moral practice

76
Q

How does Kant arrive at the 2nd formulation of the categorical imperative

A

Revolves around Kant’s distinction between rational beings and ordinary objects of inclination, which Kant terms ‘things’. If there was no need for them in pursuing a certain end then they would have no value. It has worth instrumentally rather than instrinsically

Things are set opposite to rational beings, whose possession of reason as part of their nature makes them ends in themselves, not to be used as means towards any other end. Our rational existence/humanity give as an absolute unconditional worth

77
Q

Debate whether the 2nd formulation makes sense

A

Some critics have said that this formulation is an example of intuitive understanding than having a purely a priori basis. There is not necessarily anything within reason itself to state why reason is important, or why because one person holding their rational existence as important should necessarily view anyone else’s as the same. For instance, one could take the position of solipsism

On the other hand, conclusions like solipsism seem to take a larger intuitive jump that reconising that everyone else, similar with regards to rational existence, as deserving of respect through treating them as an end in themselves

However, the idea that an ethic that is supposed to have its grounds in reason takes an inductive leap of any sort, even if this is relatively small, is a problem for Kant

We also use people as a means to an ends every day when we pay for labour and services. We can make a distinction between when this transaction is fair and equal (paying a fair price for a taxi) and when someone is being used merely as a means to an end (putting a gun to the driver’s head to get a free ride). However, where to draw the line between these two possibilities is a subjective term. For instance, if we buy fast fashion are we guilty of using those underpaid workers as a means to an end. What constitutes a fair price for a service is a subjective idea

The idea that rationality is the basis for why people should be respected as ends in themselves does not provide protection for the incapacitated and the mentally ill

78
Q

How can the third formulation be seen as bringing a social aspect

A

Because one acts towards this perfect possible Kingdom, rather than just within the context of their own lives

79
Q

Why is the third formulation somewhat ironic

A

Because many of the criticisms of his deontological system is due to its perceived lack of usefulness or applicability to everyday morality