lecture 3 Flashcards
The concept of political system
Draw picture David Easton’s concept
- This ambitious model sets out to explain the entire political process, as well as the function of major political actors, through the application of what is called
systems analysis. - A system is an organized or complex whole, a set of interrelated and interdependent parts that form a collective entity.
- In the case of the political system, a linkage exists between what Easton calls ‘inputs’ and ‘outputs’. Inputs into the political system consist of demands and supports from the general public.
- Demands can range from pressure for higher living standards, improved employment prospects, and more generous welfare payments to greater protection for minority and individual rights.
- Supports, on the other hand, are ways in which the public contributes to the political system by paying taxes, offering compliance, and being willing to participate in public life.
- Outputs consist of the decisions and actions of government, including the making of policy, the passing
of laws, the imposition of taxes, and the allocation of public funds. Clearly, these outputs generate ‘feedback’ which, in turn, shapes further demands and supports. The key insight offered by Easton’s model is that the political system tends towards long-term equilibrium or political stability, as its survival depends on outputs being brought into line with inputs. - However, it is vital to remember that conceptual models are at best simplifications of the reality they seek to explain. They are merely devices for drawing
out understanding; they are not reliable knowledge. - In the case of Easton’s model, for example, political parties and interest groups are portrayed as ‘gatekeepers’, the central function of which is to regulate the flow of inputs into the political system.
- Although this may be one of their significant functions, parties and interest groups also manage public perceptions, and thereby help to shape the nature of public demands. In short, these are more interesting and more complex institutions in reality than the systems model suggests. In the same way, Easton’s model is more effective in explaining how and why political systems respond to popular pressures than it is in explaining why they employ repression and coercion, as, to some degree, all do.
The interest in classifying
■ Comparison leads to understanding
■ Comparison leads to evaluation
Classification criteria
Draw Aristotle’s typology
Key regime features
Political factors
Economic factors
Cultural factors
Totalitarianism
■ All-encompassing system of political rule
■ A six-point syndrome (Friedrich and Brzezinski, 1963)
1. An official ideology
2. A one-party state, usually led by an all-powerful leader
3. A system of terroristic policing
4. A monopoly of the means of mass communication
5. A monopoly of the means of armed combat
6. State control of all aspects of economic life
Authoritarianism
■ Authority exercised regardless of popular consent
■ Individual liberties suppressed
Authoritarianism is a belief in, or practice of, government ‘from above’, in which authority is exercised regardless of popular consent. Authoritarianism thus differs from authority, as the latter rests on legitimacy, and so arises ‘from below’. Authoritarian regimes emphazise the claims of authority over those of individual liberty. However, authoritarianism is usually distinguished from totalitarianism. Authoritarianism, associated with monarchical absolutism, traditional dictatorships, and most forms of military rule, seeks to exclude the masses from politics rather than abolish civil society.
Democracy
The origins of the term ‘democracy’ can be traced back to Ancient Greece. Like other
words ending in ‘cracy’ (for example, autocracy, aristocracy and bureaucracy),
demo cracy is derived from the Greek word kratos, meaning power, or rule.
Democracy thus means ‘rule by the demos’ (the demos referring to ‘the people’,
although the Greeks originally used this to mean ‘the poor’ or ‘the many’).
However, the simple notion of ‘rule by the people’ does not get us very far. The
problem with democracy has been its very popularity, a popularity that has
threatened the term’s undoing as a meaningful political concept.
Amongst the meanings that
have been attached to the word ‘democracy’ are the following:
a system of rule by the poor and disadvantaged
a form of government in which the people rule themselves directly and
con tinuously, without the need for professional politicians or public offi-
cials
a society based on equal opportunity and individual merit, rather than hierarchy
and privilege
a system of welfare and redistribution aimed at narrowing social inequalities
a system of decision-making based on the principle of majority rule
a system of rule that secures the rights and interests of minorities by placing
checks upon the power of the majority
a means of filling public offices through a competitive struggle for the
popular vote
a system of government that serves the interests of the people regardless of
their participation in political life.
the people’.
How far should popular extend?
■ The issue of boundaries between the public and private realm
Models of democracy that have been
constructed on the basis of liberal individualism have usually proposed that
democracy be restricted to political life, with politics being narrowly defined.
From this perspective, the purpose of democracy is to establish, through some
process of popular participation, a framework of laws within which individuals
can conduct their own affairs and pursue their private interests. Democratic
solutions, then, are appropriate only for matters that specifically relate to the community; used in other circumstances, democracy amounts to an infringement
of liberty. Not uncommonly, this fear of democracy is most acute in the
case of direct or participatory democracy.
However, an alternative view of democracy is often developed by, for example,
socialists and radical democrats. In radical democracy, democracy is seen not as
a means of laying down a framework within which individuals can go about their
own business but, rather, as a general principle that is applicable to all areas of
social exist ence. People are seen as having a basic right to participate in the
making of any de cisions that affect their lives, with democracy simply being the
collective process through which this is done. This position is evident in socialist
demands for the collectivization of wealth and the introduction of workers’ selfmanagement,
both of which are seen as ways of democratizing economic life.
Instead of endorsing mere political democracy, socialists have therefore called for
‘social democracy’ or ‘economic democracy’. Feminists, similarly, have
demanded the democratization of family life, understood as the right of all to participate in the making of decisions in the domestic or private sphere. From this
perspective, democracy is regarded as a friend of liberty, not as its enemy. Only
when such principles are ignored can oppression and exploitation flourish.
How should the people rule?
Most conceptions of democracy are based on the principle of ‘government by the
people’. This implies that, in effect, people govern themselves – that they participate
in making the crucial decisions that structure their lives and determine the
fate of their society. This participation can take a number of forms. In
the case of direct democracy, popular participation entails direct and continuous
involvement in decision-making, through devices such as referendums (see p.
201), mass meetings, or even interactive television. The alternative and more
common form of democratic participation is the act of voting, which is the
central feature of what is usually called ‘representative democracy’. When citizens
vote, they do not so much make the decisions that structure their own lives as
choose who will make those decisions on their behalf. What gives voting its
democratic character, however, is that, provided that the election is competitive,
it empowers the public to ‘kick the devils out’, and it thus makes politicians
publicly accountable.
There are also models of democracy that are built on the principle of
‘government for the people’, and that allow little possibility for public participation
of any kind, direct or in direct. The most grotesque example of this was found
in the so-called ‘totalitarian democracies’ that developed under fascist dictators
such as Mussolini and Hitler. The democratic credentials of such regimes
were based on the claim that the ‘leader’, and the leader alone, articulated the
genuine interests of the people, thus implying that a ‘true’ democracy can be
equated with an absolute dictatorship. In such cases, popular rule meant
nothing more than ritualized submission to the will of an all-powerful leader,
orchestrated through rallies, marches and demonstrations. This was sometimes
portrayed as plebiscitary democracy. Although totalitarian democracies have
proved to be a travesty of the conventional notion of democratic rule, they
demonstrate the tension that can exist between ‘government by the people’ (or
popular participation), and ‘government for the people’ (rule in the public
interest). Advocates of representative democracy, for example, have wished to
confine popular participation in politics to the act of voting, precisely because
they fear that the general public lack the wisdom, education and experience to
rule wisely on their own behalf.
Who are the people?
One of the core features of democracy is the principle of political equality, the
notion that political power should be distributed as widely and as evenly as
possible. the answer is simple: ‘the people’, surely refers to all the people; that is, the entire population of the country. In practice, however, every democratic system has restricted
political participation, sometimes severely.
As noted, early Greek writers usually used demos to refer to ‘the many’: that
is, the disadvantaged and usually propertyless masses. Democracy therefore
implied not political equality, but a bias towards the poor. In Greek city-states,
political participation was restricted to a tiny proportion of the population, male
citizens over the age of 20, thereby excluding all women, slaves and foreigners.
Strict restrictions on voting also existed in most western states until well into the
twentieth century, usually in the form of a property qualification or the exclusion
of women. Universal suffrage was not established in the UK until 1928,
when women gained full voting rights. In the USA, it was not achieved until the
early 1960s, when African-American people in many Southern states were able
to vote for the first time, and in Switzerland universal suffrage was established in
1971 when women were eventually enfranchised. Nevertheless, an important
restriction continues to be practised in all democratic systems in the form of the
exclusion of children from political participation, although the age of majority
ranges from 21 down to as low as 15.
Technical restrictions are also often placed on, for example, the certifiably
insane and imprisoned criminals. Although ‘the people’ is now accepted as meaning virtually all adult citizens, the term can be construed in a number of different ways. The people, for
instance, can be viewed as a single, cohesive body, bound together by a common
or collective interest: in this sense, the people are one and indivisible. Such a view
tends to generate a model of democracy that, like Rousseau’s (see p. 97) theory,
examined in the next main section, focuses upon the ‘general will’ or collective
will, rather than the ‘private will’ of each individual. Alternatively, as division and
disagreement exist within all communities, ‘the people’ may in practice be taken
to mean ‘the majority’. In this case, democracy comes to mean the strict application
of the principle of majority rule. This can, nevertheless, mean that democracy
degenerates into the ‘tyranny of the majority’. Finally, there is the issue of
the body of people within which democratic politics should operate. Where
should be the location or ‘site’ of democracy? Although, thanks to the potency of
political nationalism, the definition ‘the people’ is usually understood in national
terms, the ideas of local democracy and, in the light of globalization (see p. 142),
cosmopolitan democracy (discussed in the final section of the chapter) have
also been advanced
Direct democracy
Direct democracy (sometimes ‘classical’, ‘participatory’,
or ‘radical’ democracy) is based on the direct, unmediated
and continuous participation of citizens in the
tasks of government. Direct democracy thus obliterates
the distinction between government and the governed,
and between the state and civil society; it is a system
of popular self-government. It was achieved in ancient
Athens through a form of government by mass
meeting; its most common modern manifestation is
the use of the referendum (see p. 201). The merits of
direct democracy include the following:
It heightens the control that citizens can exercise
over their own destinies, as it is the only pure form
of democracy.
It creates a better-informed and more politically
sophisticated citizenry, and thus it has educational
benefits.
It enables the public to express their own views and
interests without having to rely on self-serving
politicians.
It ensures that rule is legitimate, in the sense that
people are more likely to accept decisions that they
have made themselves.
Representative democracy
Representative democracy is a limited and indirect
form of democracy. It is limited in that popular participation
in government is infrequent and brief, being
restricted to the act of voting every few years. It is indirect
in that the public do not exercise power themselves;
they merely select those who will rule on their
behalf. This form of rule is democratic only insofar as
representation (see p. 197) establishes a reliable and
effective link between the government and the
governed. This is sometimes expressed in the notion of
an electoral mandate (see p. 200). The strengths of
representative democracy include the following:
It offers a practicable form of democracy (direct
popular participation is achievable only in small
communities).
It relieves ordinary citizens of the burden of
decision-making, thus making possible a division
of labour in politics.
It allows government to be placed in the hands of
those with better education, expert knowledge and
greater experience.
It maintains stability by distancing ordinary citizens
from politics, thereby encouraging them to accept
compromise.
Models of democracy
Four contrasting models of democracy can be identified as follows: classical democracy protective democracy developmental democracy people’s democracy.
classical democracy
The classical model of democracy is based on the polis, or city-state, of Ancient
Greece, and particularly on the system of rule that developed in the largest and
most powerful Greek city-state, Athens. The form of direct democracy that operated
in Athens during the fourth and fifth centuries BCE is often portrayed as the
only pure or ideal system of popular participation. Nevertheless, although the
model had considerable impact on later thinkers such as Rousseau and Marx (see
p. 41), Athenian democracy (see p. 95) developed a very particular kind of direct
popular rule, one that has only a very limited application in the modern world.
Athenian democracy amounted to a form of government by mass meeting.
What made Athenian democracy so remarkable was the level of political
activity of its citizens. Not only did they participate in regular meetings of the
Assembly, but they were also, in large numbers, prepared to shoulder the responsibility
of public office and decision-making. The most influential contemporaneous
critic of this form of democracy was the philosopher Plato (see p. 13).
Plato attacked the principle of political equality on the grounds that the mass of
the people possess neither the wisdom nor the experience to rule wisely on their
own behalf. His solution, advanced in The Republic, was that government be
placed in the hands of a class of philosopher kings, Guardians, whose rule would
amount to a kind of enlightened dictatorship. On a practical level, however, the
principal drawback of Athenian democracy was that it could operate only by
excluding the mass of the population from political activity. Participation was
restricted to Athenian-born males who were over 20 years of age. Slaves (the
majority of the population), women and foreigners had no political rights whatsoever. Indeed, Athenian citizens were able to devote so much of their lives
to politics only because slavery relieved them of the need to engage in arduous
labour, and the confinement of women to the private realm freed men from
domestic responsibilities. Nevertheless, the classical model of direct and continuous
popular participation in political life has been kept alive in, for instance, the
township meetings of New England in the USA, the communal assemblies that
operate in the smaller Swiss cantons and in the wider use of referendums.
protective democracy
When democratic ideas were revived in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries,
they appeared in a form that was very different from the classical democracy of
Ancient Greece. In particular, democracy was seen less as a mechanism through
which the public could participate in political life, and more as a device through
which citizens could protect themselves from the encroachments of government,
hence ‘protective democracy’. This view appealed particularly to early liberal
thinkers whose concern was, above all, to create the widest realm of individual
liberty. The desire to protect the individual from over-mighty government was
expressed in perhaps the earliest of all democratic sentiments, Aristotle’s response
to Plato: ‘who will guard the Guardians?’.
This same concern with unchecked power was taken up in the seventeenth
century by John Locke (see p. 31), who argued that the right to vote was based
on the existence of natural rights and, in particular, on the right to property. If
government, through taxation, possessed the power to expropriate property, citizens
were entitled to protect themselves by controlling the composition of the
tax-setting body: the legislature. In other words, democracy came to mean a
system of ‘government by consent’ operating through a representative assembly.
However, Locke himself was not a democrat by modern standards, as he believed
that only property owners should vote, on the basis that only they had natural
rights that could be infringed by government. The more radical notion of
universal suffrage was advanced from the late eighteenth century onwards by
utilitarian theorists such as Jeremy Bentham and James Mill (1773–1836). The
utilitarian (see p. 353) case for democracy is also based on the need to protect or
advance individual interests. Bentham came to believe that, since all individuals
seek pleasure and the avoidance of pain, a universal franchise (conceived in his
day as manhood suffrage) was the only way of promoting ‘the greatest happiness
for the greatest number’.
However, to justify democracy on protective grounds is to provide only a
qualified endorsement of democratic rule. In short, protective democracy is but
a limited and indirect form of democracy. In practice, the consent of the
governed is exercised through voting in regular and competitive elections. This
thereby ensures the accountability of those who govern. Political equality is thus
understood in strictly technical terms to mean equal voting rights. Moreover,
this is, above all, a system of con stitutional democracy that operates within a set
of formal or informal rules that check the exercise of government power. If the
right to vote is a means of defending individual liberty, liberty must also be guaranteed
by a strictly enforced separation of powers via the creation of a separate
executive, legislature and judiciary, and by the maintenance of basic rights and
freedoms, such as freedom of expression, freedom of movement, and freedom from arbitrary arrest. Ultimately, protective democracy aims to give citizens the
widest possible scope to live their lives as they choose. It is therefore compatible
with laissez-faire capitalism (see p. 132) and the belief that individuals should be
entirely responsible for their economic and social circumstances. Protective
democracy has therefore particularly appealed to classical liberals and, in
modern politics, to supporters of the New Right.