Lecture 3 Flashcards
Continue: Schools of Ethics
Aristotelian virtue ethics is a type of virtue ethics that is based on the teachings of the Ancient Greek philosopher Aristotle. According to Aristotle, virtues are habits or dispositions that lead to a good and flourishing life. He believed that virtues are formed through practice and repetition, and the ultimate goal of human life is to achieve eudaimonia, or “happiness” or “flourishing”. Aristotle identified several virtues, including courage, prudence, justice, and temperance. He believed that virtues are the mean between the extremes, such as the mean between cowardice and recklessness being courage. He also believed that virtues are necessary for achieving eudaimonia, and that they are interrelated, with one virtue leading to another.
- be virtuous
- become a better person
- not acting properly is bad
- not acting at all is bad (cowardis)
Deontology
(Kantian) believes that rule and laws dictate the rightness and wrongness of behaviour as long as they are dealt in good faith and treats people as ends, not menas (categorical imperative).
- rules and laws, being transparent, good faith, treat people as not means (treat people how you want to be treated) and keep promises
Utilitarianism
(Mills) believes that the right decision is the one that maximizes happiness (utility) and reduces suffering.
- policy making
- whatever will make the most people happy is the right decision
- politicians, have insurance, medicine - choosing who to save
- ends justify the means
- what about the minority?
Existentialism
Believes that there is no universal meaning to reality beyond the meaning that each one of us projects, and thus one’s morality is a reflection of one’s authentic self while acting in good faith by accepting the frightening truth oof absolute freedom. Existentialism still accepts universal values of authenticity and acting in good faith.
- decide what you want to be and do that
- frightening truth of absolute freedom
The four principles of biomedical ethics
The four principles of biomedical ethics
- respect for autonomy (a norm of respecting the decision-making capacities of autonomous persons)
- free to do what they want in good faith, and with their own judgement
- told you need to take meds, you don’t have to if you don’t want to
- mental disability
- unconscious
- no age of consent
- being drunk is not, not being able to give consent
- can still say yes or no - non-maleficence (a norm of avoiding the causation of harm)
- do no harm (intention)
- saving someone from a burning car, but paralyse them
- doctors neglecting patients - by not giving meds on time by not setting an alarm - beneficence (a group of norms for providing benefits and balancing benefits against risks and costs); and
- planning to do good - justice (a group of norms for distributing benefits, risks and costs fairly)
- equal access
- no discrimination
Health care professional or actor - use these
Formalism:
Don’t go deeper than the laws
To play a game is to attempt to achieve a specific state of affairs, using only means permitted by the rules, where the rules prohibit use of more efficient in favour of less efficient means, and where the rules are accepted just because they make possible such activity
Playing a game is the voluntary attempt to overcome unnecessary obstacles
For the purpose our course, all sports are games
Following a rule book
- you can play a sport
Not following a rule book
- ou can’t playa sport
Cheat, or door - you can’t play anymore
Conventionalism
How we decide to play the game
Conventionalists argue that an adequate account of sport must appeal to collectively agreed-upon norms called “conventions”
Fred D’Agostino, the pioneer of conventionalism, maintains that the conventions that operate within a game constitute the “ethos” of the game. The ethos of the game is the “set of unofficial, implicit conventions which determine how the rules of a game are to be applied in concrete circumstances
Broad internalism (interpretivism)
Not what is sport but what it should be!
- sportsmanship
- ends and means
Sporting competition as a “mutually accepted quest for excellence through challenge
Generates a coherent and principled account of the point and purposes that underlie the game, attempting to show the game in its best light
Today students will learn to
- Recognize general features of arguments
- Distinguish between deductive and inductive arguments and evaluate them for validity, soundness, strength, and weakness
- Identify unstated premises
- Identify a balance of considerations argument and an inference to the best explanation (IBE)
- Distinguish between ethos, pathos, and logos as means of persuasion
- Use techniques for understanding and evaluating the structure and content of arguments
Arguments: general features
- an argument consists of two parts: the premise and the conclusion
- the premise is intended to provide a reason for accepting the conclusion
- a statement by itself is not an argument
- an emphasis statement is not an argument
Conclusions used as premises
- a statement can be both the conclusion of one argument and a premise in another argument
- if a premise in an argument is uncertain or controversial, the speaker may need to defend it, making it the conclusion of a new argument
- however, it is not always reasonable to keep asking for defence of each primes, as it can become unreasonable
- in the example, asking why the car has outlived its usefulness may lead to the mention of the car being hard to start, but asking why the car is hard to start may not have a clear answer
Conclusion can use premise of a different conclusion
Unstated premises and conclusion
- arguments can contain unstated assumptions or premises, such as in the example “you can’t check out books from the library without an ID. Bill won’t be able o check out at books.” Where the unstated assumption is that bill does not have an ID
- arguments can also have unstated conclusions, where the conclusion is not explicitly stated but can be inferred, such as in the example “Stacy drives a Porsche. This suggests that either she is rich or her parents are”. Where the conclusion is “either she is rich or her parents are”.
- certain words and phrases, such as “thus” consequently,” “therefore”, “so”, “hence” “accordingly” “this shows that” “this implies that” and “this suggests that” “c signal that a premise has been presented and a conclusion is about to be made.
- unstated premises are common in real life and can often be assumed as obvious
- unstated conclusions are less common than unstated premises
deductive argument
- a deductive argument is a type of argument in which the premise or premises, if true, prove or demonstrate the conclusion
- the concept of validity is important in deductive logic, which states that an argument is valid if it is not possible for the premise or premises to be true and the conclusion to be false. What is a valid argument?
- when the premise of a valid argument is true, the argument is said to be sound
- a good deductive argument has to be true and valid
Wen in doubt pick inductive reasoning
- pigeons are birds, birds all fly, legions must fly
- anyone can make a great conclusion
- need valid premise to support conclusion
- either true or false, no in between
- strong argument or weak argument
- more information you present is a better conclusion
- missing some information - better the data the better the argument/conclusion
95% of prohibited stuff scientists can’t even prove how it enhances athletes
- proof by how its not meant for humans or human studies
- do no harm principle
- so studies aren’t conducted
- they just loan them
Inductive argument
- inductive arguments are a type of argument where the premise supports the conclusion, but does not demonstrate or prove it
- support for the conclusion in inductive arguments can vary in degree and can be described as stronger or weaker
- an argument is stronger if it raises the probability of the conclusion more than a weaker argument
- in chapter 11, criteria for evaluating inductive arguments will be explained in more details
- examples of inductive arguments:
- traffic slows to a crawl after 2pm on the Bay Bridge supports but does not prove that is does the same on the Golden Gate Bridge
- if Alexandra rarely returns texts, it supports but does not prove that she probably rarely returns emails
- the fact that nobody has run a mile in less than 3 minutes does not demonstrate or prove that nobody will ever run a mile in less than 3 minutes
Sherlock Holmes
“When you have eliminated the impossible, whatever remains, however improbable, must be the truth.
Deductive
- the premise is “when you have eliminated the impossible”
- the conclusion is “whatever remains, however improbable, must be the truth”
Inductive if you havent eliminated everything else