Consequentialism & Nonconsequentialist Constraints Flashcards
act consequentialism
the morality of an action depends on the consequences brought about by the action a person took
actual consequentialism
actions are right or wrong depending on the consequences they actually bring about
actualism
when a person is deciding which action would be best, they should weigh the consequences of actions based on what their actual choices will be in the future
agent-neutral
an agent-neutral reason is a reason that applies to anybody, regardless of their particular circumstances
agent-relative
an agent-relative reason is a reason that applies only to particular individual
consequentialism
the morality of an action depends only on its consequences
constraint
limits the list of possible actions we can take to further the good
disaster-avoidance clause
if it prevents disaster then an action is permissible
doctrine of doing and allowing (DDA)
there is a significant moral difference between doing harm and merely allowing harm to happen
doctrine of double effect (DDE)
there is a moral constraint on intending evil, even when the evil will be a means to a greater good. Nonetheless, we may be permitted to employ neutral or good means to pursue a greater good, even though we foresee evil side effects if (1) the good is proportionate to the evil and (2) there is no better way to achieve this good (Kamm, 2013)
equivalence thesis
there is no intrinsic moral difference between harming and not-aiding
expected consequentialism
a person acts rightly by doing the action that has the highest level of “expected utility”
hedonism
judge actions based on how much pleasure or pain they produce
impartial
everyone’s welfare counts equally in determining the deontic status of an action
inviolability
entails a protection of an individual’s negative rights
negative right
a right to non-interference
nonconsequentialism
denies that the rightness or wrongness of our conduct is determined solely by the goodness or badness of the consequences of our acts or the rules to which those acts conform
partial nonconsequentialism
might advocate prerogatives but no constraints (Scheffler, 1982) or constraints but no prerogatives (Kagan, 1989)
pluralist consequentialism
actions should be judged on a plurality of consequences (e.g. justice, happiness, knowledge)
positive right
right to self-authority , self-mastery
possibilism
when a person is deciding which action would be best, they should weigh the consequences of actions based on what the possible actions they would be capable of taking in the future
prerogatives
moral prerogatives permit an agent to (1) act in ways that do not maximise the impartial good, and (2) act for reasons that stem from his personal perspective, rather than from the perspective of an impartial judge (Kamm, 2013)
principle of permissible harm (PPH)
it is permissible for (1) greater good and (2) means that have greater good as their noncausal flip side to cause a lesser evil, but not permissible for an act (3) to require a lesser evil as a means to greater good, or (4) to directly cause a lesser evil as a side effect when the act has greater good as mere causal effect
rule consequentialism
an action A is right iff A is in accordance with a rule which if generally followed / accepted makes the outcome best
satisficing consequentialism
to perform an action that is “good enough” with respect to its consequences, even if some alternative action would have even better consequences
subjective consequentialism
a person’s actions are right or wrong depending on what they thought the consequences would be
universal
everyone whose welfare will be affected by one’s action counts morally
utilitarianism
the moral worth of an action is determined by how much happiness or suffering it brings to the world, and therefore people should always do whatever will bring about the most happiness to the most people
veil of ignorance
moral reasoning device designed to promote impartial decision-making by denying decision-makers access to potentially biasing information about who will benefit most or least from the available options
what are two key features of consequentialism?
universal = holds that everyone whose welfare will be affected by one’s action counts morally
impartial = everyone’s welfare counts equally in determining the deontic status of an action
what is the difference between actual and expected consequentialism?
actual consequences: to act rightly is to do whatever produces the best consequences
expected consequences: a person acts rightly by doing the action that has the highest level of “expected utility”
- expected utility is a combination of the good (or bad) effects that one predicts will result from an action and the probability of those effects occurring
what is Smart’s drowning Hitler example? what is its relevance to the debate between actual vs expected consequences?
imagine the action of a person who, in 1938, saves someone from drowning.
while we generally regard saving a drowning person as the right thing to do and praise people for such actions, the person saved from drowning in this case was Adolf Hitler
had Hitler drowned, millions of other people might have been saved from suffering and death between 1938 and 1945
if utilitarianism evaluates the rescuer’s actions based on actual consequences, then the rescuer did the wrong thing
if utilitarianism judges the rescuer’s action by its foreseeable, expected consequences, then the rescuer did the right thing
should consequentialism be used as a theory of rightness or as a decision procedure?
most consequentialists claim that it should be a theory of rightness
- “it is not to be expected that this process should be strictly pursued previously to every moral judgement” (Bentham, 1789)
a criterion of the right can be useful at a higher level by helping us choose among available decision procedures & refine our decision procedures as circumstances change and we gain more experience and knowledge
how does understanding consequentialism as a theory of rightness help defend against some criticisms.
a consequentialist criterion of right implies that it would not be morally right to use consequentialism as a decision procedure in cases where it would not maximise utility to try to calculate utilities before acting
if the principle of utility is used as a criterion of the right rather than as a decision procedure, then classical utilitarianism does not require that anyone know the total consequences of anything before making a decision
a criterion of the right can be useful at a higher level by helping us choose among available decision procedures & refine our decision procedures as circumstances change and we gain more experience and knowledge
why is consequentialism unlikely or unhelpful as a decision-procedure?
unforeseen & unforeseeable consequences
what intuition supports act consequentialism?
most people agree that we morally ought to improve the world where possible and acting to bring about the best outcomes seems a natural way to achieve this
what are the main objections to act consequentialism?
main objections to act consequentialism
- unable to make sense of familiar moral options
- unable to make sense of familiar moral constraints
- consequentialism operates with a dubious notion of goodness
- consequentialism is self-defeating
- consequentialism gives no practical guidance at all
what is the demandingness objection to act consequentialism?
requirement to maximise utility strikes many people as too demanding because it interferes with the personal decisions that most of us feel should be left up to the individual
the demandingness objection specifically takes issue with the extent to which a theory is demanding on the individual’s self-interest
leaves no room for actions that are permissible yet do not bring about the best consequences
- everything that is suboptimal is impermissible
what is Singer’s version of consequentialism?
- suffering and death from lack of food, shelter and medical care are bad
- if it in our power to prevent something bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything of comparable moral importance, then we ought, morally, to do it
- it makes no moral difference whether the person I can help is a neighbour’s child ten yards from me or a Bengali whose name I shall never know, ten thousand miles away
- the principle makes no distinction between cases in which I am the only person who could possibly do anything and cases in which I am just one among millions in the same position
very demanding form of consequentialism
what are some issues with Singer’s version of consequentialism?
very demanding (although Singer believes morality should be this demanding, no one said it should be easy)
premises 3 & 4 reject to commonly held intuitions about our moral obligations
what is the supererogation objection to consequentialism?
this objection deals with the idea that a plausible principle of beneficence should not require too big a personal sacrifice in order to help strangers
due to agent-neutrality, consequentialism seems unable to make sense of special obligations we have to particular individuals or groups (e.g. family)
what does Wolf mean by act consequentialism being a “morality for saints”?
moral saint: “a person whose every action is as morally good as possible, a person, that is, who is as morally worthy as can be”