The Source of Legal Obligations Flashcards
Obligations:
- key question re obligation to obey the law
- Raz on law’s effect
- Dworkin on law’s effect
- Prudential reasons?
- not that there’s always an obligation to obey every law, but rather how law changes our reasons, which particular reasons, and whether these reasons count as obligations.
- Raz – laws create exclusionary reasons and legal duties are therefore these exclusionary reasons
- Dworkin (Greenburg, Hershovitz, Stavropolous): no need to discuss exclusionary reasons etc. – the law doesn’t have exclusionary effect. It gives ordinary first order reasons (albeit strong ones), so the presence of exclusionary reasons isn’t an objection to them.
What kinds of reasons does the law give us? - Prudential reasons (though this isn’t an obligation – it’s more like reasons to avoid dangerous animals etc.)
Introduction
Do we have a general obligation to obey the laws of our legal system?
- what do liberal anarchists argue?
- what if acting in conformity with the directives is the right thing to do?
- how have legal scholars responded re locating the general obligation to obey the law? (4 points)
- 2 follow up questions:
- Liberal anarchists famously argued that acceding to the claims of authority of one’s legal system—even if it is a reasonably good legal system—is fundamentally incompatible with one’s autonomy. Therefore, they suggested, one should never comply with legal directives (or the directives of any supposed authority, for that matter).
- Of course, acting in conformity with certain directives will often be the right thing to do, but that is coincidental and therefore beside the point.
- In response to the anarchist challenge, scholars have tried to locate a general obligation to obey the law in a legal system’s effectiveness in solving coordination problems, the substantive justice of its laws, its democratic decision-making procedures or the true community it fosters.
- If they fail and we are forced to agree with the anarchists that there is indeed no general obligation to obey the law,
- does that still leave open the possibility of a legitimate legal system?
- Even if it turns out that there is no general obligation to obey the law, is there nonetheless a right way to relate to the laws of a legitimate legal system?
R. Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970) ch 1: “The Conflict between Authority and Autonomy
I - The concept of authority
- definition of a state and its distinctive characteristic?
- definition of authority?
- First question: under what conditions and for what reasons does one man have supreme authority over another?
- The state is a group of persons who exercise supreme authority within a given territory, and may include all the persons who fall under its authority. Its distinctive characteristic is supreme authority – sovereignty
- Authority is the right to command and correlatively the right to be obeyed, distinguished from power: the ability to compel compliance.
- We must demonstrate by an a priori argument that there can be forms of human community in which some men have a moral right to rule. Legitimate (de jure) authority thus concerns the grounds and sources of moral obligations; de facto states are simply states whose subjects believe it to be legitimate – although they may be wrong. Since some people do so believe, there are de facto states.
R. Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970) ch 1: “The Conflict between Authority and Autonomy
II - The concept of autonomy
- what is the fundamental assumption in moral philosophy? where does the obligation NOT derive from?
- what does a responsible individual acknowledge?
- how might we say a man is autonomous
- how might we say he is free?
- can man abdicate his autonomy?
- can man give up responsibility for his actions?
- The fundamental assumption of moral philosophy is that men are responsible for their actions; this obligation does not derive from man’s freedom of will alone, for more is required in taking responsibility than freedom of choice.
- A responsible individual does not imply that he always does what is right but only that he does not neglect the duty of attempting to ascertain what is right. He does acknowledge himself bound by moral constraints, but he insists that he alone is the judge of those constraints.
- Since the responsible man arrives at moral decisions which he expresses to himself in the form of imperatives, we may say that he gives laws to himself or is self legislating – autonomous.
4, He may do what another tells him but not because he has been told to do it – he is therefore, in the political sense of the word, free.
- Since man’s responsibility for his actions is a consequence of his capacity for choice, he cannot give it up or put it aside, but he can refuse to acknowledge it – therefore, man can forfeit his autonomy at will: he can decide to obey the commands of another without making any attempt to determine for himself whether what is commanded is good or wise. We frequently forfeit our autonomy – by giving to the force of tradition or bureaucracy.
- This is not the same as the false assertion that a man can give up responsibility for his actions - the moral condition demands that we acknowledge responsibility and achieve autonomy wherever and whenever possible.
R. Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970) ch 1: “The Conflict between Authority and Autonomy
III - The conflict between authority and autonomy
- what is the defining mark of the state?
- what is the primary obligation of man?
- why is anarchism consistent with autonomy?
- does the feeling of a special obligation to the law have an objective basis?
- is all authority equally wrothless according to the anarchist?
- why is a de jure legitimate state vacuous?
- The defining mark of the state is authority, the right to rule.
- The primary obligation of man is autonomy, the refusal to be ruled. Insofar as a man fulfills his obligation to make himself the author of his decisions we will resist the state’s claim to have authority over him; he will deny that he has a duty to obey the laws of the state simply because they are laws.
- Thus, anarchism is the only political doctrine consistent with the virtue of autonomy. An anarchist may grant the necessity of complying with the law under certain circumstances or for the time being, but he will never view the commands of the state as legitimate, as having a binding moral force.
- The anarchist tells me my feeling of a special obligation to obey its laws is purely sentimental and has no objective moral basis.
- All authority is equally illegitimate, although of course not therefore equally worth or unworthy of support
- . If all men have a continuing obligation to achieve the highest degree of autonomy possible, then there would appear to be no state whose subjects have amoral obligation to obey its commands. Hence the concept of a de jure legitimate state would appear to be vacuous, and philosophical anarchism would seem to be the only reasonable political belief for an enlightened man.
Bix, Jurisprudence: Theory and Context
Intro
- what is the seminal q?
- what do most writers assume?
- reasons for obeying the law?
- what is the focus of the debate?
- what are the various theories?
- what are the various scenarios?
- The question is whether there is a moral obligation to obey the law, a moral obligation that attaches to a rule simply because of its legal validity, i.e. its membership within a legal system.
- Most writers assume:
1) A generally just legal system
2) There is a prima facie obligation that can be overridden if a stronger moral obligation requires a contrary action - Reasons for obeying the law:
1) Prudential reasons (fear of imprisonment or fine)
2) Habit (easier to obey the law unreflectively rather than calculating the moral and prudential factors on each occasion) - These reasons aren’t the focus of the debate – the question is whether the legal status of a command, by itself, without more, adds any moral reasons for doing/not doing an action.
- Various theories:
1) Consent
2) Gratitude
3) Reciprocity
4) Consequences - In all cases, the difficult scenario is one where there is seemingly no risk of harming anyone, and the disobedience seems like it would go undetected (ex. stop sign at 3AM).
Bix, Jurisprudence: Theory and Context
I – Consent
- thesis?
- steps to the argument?
(i) step + possible response?
(ii) step 2 + response? - what is the real question?
- what is a possible response?
- Thesis: by some action (voting, accepting government benefits, not leaving the country) or inaction, we have implicitly consented to obeying society’s law.
- Steps to this argument:
(i) A certain action constitutes “consent” to obeying the society’s laws – response is that these activities cannot be properly understood as consent, because a) citizens do not perceive of their action that way, and b) do not have reasonable alternatives.
(ii) Consent in this way leads to a moral obligation to obey the law - even if these activities can constitute the consent, consent doesn’t necessarily equate an obligation to obey the society’s laws. Why?
a. Acts of consent may have limited force: a mere promise is not sufficient to maintain large moral claims, like creating a moral obligation to do something a) on one-sided terms (paint your house for $1), b) immoral (kill your father), c) give up one’s autonomy (do anything you told me to for a month). In the same way, mere consent may not be sufficient to justify creating a broad obligation to obey whatever the government might enact from that day onward.
- The real question: how do we create moral obligations for ourselves, and what are the limits of these obligations? The extent to which consent can create, waive or defeat legal and moral obligations is a difficult theoretical question – thus, consent offers at best, a partial response.
- Possible response: consent only creates an obligation to obey a generally just regime, not just any regime – but even if this is true, is it consent, or the justice of the regime itself, that creates the obligation to obey, consent merely working to limit certain types of legitimate complaint by the citizen?
Bix, Jurisprudence: Theory and Context
II – Consequentialist approach (Hobbes, Honoré)
- thesis
- Hobbes?
- Honore
(i) response?
(ii) counter-argument to the response
- Thesis: the obligation arises from the bad consequences to society if people did not have such an obligation.
- Hobbes (extreme version): the law is to be obeyed even when it is unjust, because the alternative is the chaos of the state of nature, the law of all against all (Hobbes, Leviathan: “though of so unlimited a [Sovereign] Power, men may fancy many evil consequences, yet the consequences of the want of it, which is the perpetual war of every man against his neighbour; are much worse”)
- Honoré: if the initial presumption is that the law need not be obeyed, then people will tend more often to disregard the law than if the initial presumption is for obedience, leading to an “attitude of disobedience” and the breakdown of the order and cooperation needed for society to function
(i) Response: fear of legal sanctions and pre-existing moral commitments are enough to prevent the consequences of disobedience
- though not really - notwithstanding the fact that many crimes do go unaddressed, great psychological comfort comes from the fact that we are all abiding by the same (overarching) rules. Even though in a city like London, cultural norms differ, the knowledge that there is a common denominator in these norms fosters solidarity, an essential evolutionary requirement as a remarkably social creature. The challenge, as seen with the EU project, is in finding the balance.
Further, taken to its extreme, such ‘solidarity’ creates rigid borders and can drown out other values i.e. differing views. But in a moderated form, it provides enough structure to demarcate the boundaries of our rules, whilst leaving scope for debate and development. Such a vision of the law can be supported by reference to an experiment in a children’s playground. Clearly defined boundaries led to the children wandering to the very edge of those boundaries. However, the absence of any boundaries meant that the majority stayed much closer to the central building.
Bix, Jurisprudence: Theory and Context
III – Benefit or gratitude (Plato)
- thesis?
- analogy to…? - responses?
- 4 points
- Thesis: it is immoral for those who have received substantial benefits from the state not to respond with the same obligation that governments ask in return – obedience to the law (by analogy to the duty of children to their parents).
- Responses:
- children don’t owe parents the obligation to let them determine all our future choices – so is gratitude to government sufficient to give it moral authority over our actions?
- we can only owe a moral obligation if we voluntarily accept such benefits and intend to continue to do so, whereas most people don’t have the power to waive their rights to receive them
- further, many would prefer limited interference by the state!
- On the other hand, the law does coordinate activities and that given that we inadvertently take advantage of the effects of this coordination i.e. we can safely drive to work knowing which side of the road to drive on, the abide so others can carry out their
The law is therefore a traffic light, finding workable combinations to give as much liberty (given that our prevailing moral political philosophy stems from Mill) to all citizens.
Bix, Jurisprudence: Theory and Context
IV – A duty to support and to further just institutions (Rawls)
- thesis
- response?
- Thesis: the natural law position that if laws are just, they have the power of binding in conscience, a power which comes from the Eternal Law from which they are derived (Aquinas).
- Responses: even if this is true, it doesn’t create a general moral obligation to obey every law on every occasion, as many instances of disobedience simply do not undermine just institutions.
Bix, Jurisprudence: Theory and Context
V – Fairness or reciprocity (Hart)
Thesis: obedience is not a duty to the state but a duty to one’s fellow citizens – “when a number of persons conduct any joint enterprise according to rules and thus restrict their liberty those who have submitted to their restrictions when required have a right to a similar submission from those who have benefitted by their submission” (Hart, Are There Any Natural Rights?). Someone who disobeys the law is unfairly taking advantage of other people’s sacrifices.
Bix, Jurisprudence: Theory and Context
VI – There is no moral obligation to obey the law (Fuller)
- what does Fuller argue?
- what does Raz argue?
- what is an objection to Raz’s view?
- what do sceptics argue re obligation to obey the law?
- questions to distinguish?
- what does Smith argue?
- In the course of the Hart-Fuller debate Fuller argues that if, according to legal positivism, the validity of a law is separate from its moral value, then how can the legal positivists speak of a “moral dilemma” about whether to obey a morally dubious law? (Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Law). Just because something is required by law, it is not by itself a moral reason for doing that action.
- But some legal positivists accept that the legal status of a norm may give it no intrinsic moral weight (Raz) – they don’t argue that we should never obey the law, but only that the moral reasons must go beyond the simple “because the law says so”.
- Raz: we have a moral obligation to obey the law if and when we believe that we are more likely to make the morally best choice by following the law than by making our own judgment (because the legislator heard expert testimony, because of coordination problems). But the most common situation is that what the law requires is when the action is the moral thing to do, regardless of what the law says. - [Objection: how can you know that you have a better idea of what is morally right than the legislature?]
- Sceptics say that the arguments for a general moral obligation to obey the law is insufficient to ground a general obligation – if disobeying a law causes no harm and doesn’t create a bad example, how is it going to undermine a just institution or a joint enterprise? Why should consent or a duty of fair play/gratitude extend to all laws – even where disobedience is harmless. Why should we continue to have the obligation to obey a coordinating law if it has become clear that it failed at coordinating?
- Questions to distinguish:
1) ethical question: what should I do in this situation?
2) meta-ethical question: what is the set of beliefs and attitudes we want or need the public to hold?
3) political question: from perspective x, what is the set of beliefs and attitudes we want or need the public to hold? (not covered here) - Smith: even if there is a moral obligation, it carries little moral weight because:
1) a seriously immoral act does not become significantly more or less culpable depending on whether the action is legally permitted or not
2) we are slow to condemn someone for breaking the law until we find out which law was broken
Bix, Jurisprudence: Theory and Context
VII – Connections
This topic is connected to more basic questions of:
Difference in adopting natural law vs positivist view
This topic is connected to more basic questions of:
1) Moral theory (what grounds our moral duties: benefit? consent? cooperation? consequences? necessity? interdependence?)
2) Legal theory (how do we determine the existence or validity of a law or legal system?)
If you start with traditional natural law theory, then your conclusion about whether something is “law” will incorporate much of the answer about whether one has an obligation to obey the law (ex. you have an obligation to obey just laws, and a minimal obligation to obey unjust laws for public compliance so as not to undermine a generally just legal system).
But if you’re a legal positivist, then because the validity of law is independent from its merits, then you need to find your answers elsewhere.
Penner, Textbook on Jurisprudence
I – A necessary prima facie moral obligation to obey the law
It was assumed that for the State and the law to function, it was necessary that subjects of the law had a prima facie (i.e. defeasible) obligation to obey the law – so the debate is how the obligation should be explained. This is the starting point of:
Penner, Textbook on Jurisprudence
A - Plato/Socrates (Classical Greco-Roman natural law)
Plato, in The Last Days of Socrates, purports to present statements of Socrates in relation to law and the duty of obedience:
- Apology: the State has no right to demand that a person commit evil or injustice – where this is in fact demanded, the only honorable course is refusal.
- Crito: addresses the different question of where the state (through its law) doesn’t command wrong of an individual but does wrong to him.
o Three grounds of obligation to comply with the law, of which an analogy with the relationship of parent and child and State and citizen: the obligation arises from gratitude for the law maintaining a system in which the individual has chosen to reside (assumes that individuals are free to depart). By disobeying, an individual attempts to destroy the law and the social fabric that it supports and which that individual must be taken to have accepted by remaining in the state.
o So if you don’t approve you have three options: move, persuade the state to amend the law, or obey. This assumes that 1) persuasion is possible and 2) legitimate departure is possible. But in practice this may not be true (ex. potential victims of genocide in the Third Reich can neither persuade nor depart – should they then submit willingly to slaughter?)
Inconsistency between the argument for disobedience in Apology and obedience in Crito, possibly explained by a distinction between a duty to do no wrong to others, and a duty to accept an unjust infliction pursuant to an obligation already accepted. So while Plato denies the right of the State to command evildoing, it denies simultaneously the right of an individual to refuse submission when wrongful acts are commanded by the law to be done to him (subject to persuasion and prior departure).
Penner, Textbook on Jurisprudence
B - Finnis (Natural Law Revival)
4 types of obligations
dismissal of these into separate disciplines
division between moral and collateral moral
Four types of obligations: 1) sanction-based (Bentham), 2) intra-systemic formal (Austin), 3) moral (Hart) and 4) collateral moral (natural law theories).
The dismissal of some of these into other disciplines is unsound jurisprudential method. The idea of “obligation” is not a singular phenomenon but a combination of different obligatory factors (coercive, formal and moral).
The division between moral and collateral moral is that by disobeying a law (even a bad one) a person places at risk the whole legal system and there is therefore a “collateral” moral obligation to obey such a law notwithstanding its immorality.
Penner, Textbook on Jurisprudence
C – Theories justifying a general moral obligation
1 – Consent
- problem
- response
- Problem = absence of actual consent.
- Response = notional consent (i.e actual consent is unnecessary where consenting would be a reasonable thing to do), but this dispenses with consent altogether rather than depending upon it, because if it would not be reasonable to consent, then actual consent can’t justify it, and if it is reasonable, actual consent is unnecessary.
Penner, Textbook on Jurisprudence
C – Theories justifying a general moral obligation
2 – Fair play/benefit and burden
- what is it?
- does it justify an obligation to a general system of law?
- Between state and citizen
- Between citizens (insisting on one’s own legal rights entails respecting the legal rights of others)
But the obligation we’re trying to justify is a general moral obligation to obey every law of the system just because it is a law of the system – fair play is a moral obligation of its own, and complying with it doesn’t justify complying with every rule that forms part of whatever body of laws is laid down by an authority (indeed some laws even contribute to unfairness: tax regimes).
Penner, Textbook on Jurisprudence
C – Theories justifying a general moral obligation
3 – Violation sets an example to others (Finnis)
2 counter-arguments
It encourages disobedience causing harm to the legal system, making it less effective. This is hopeless:
1) Certain instances of disobedience may shock people and encourage greater obedience
2) Many acts of disobedience would never be detected
Penner, Textbook on Jurisprudence
D – Denying a general moral obligation
RAZ
- people who respect their communities
- is this sufficient to ground a general obligation to obey the law?
- what paradox does Raz highlight?
- what 2 categories of law does Raz distinguish?
- what are the different rationales for obeying each?
- Raz: certain people, i.e. those who respect and are more or less deeply committted to their communities, may come under a general obligation to obey the law as an expression of that respect, but that does not ground a general obligation for everyone (by analogy with friendship creating certain special, expressive reasons to act in certain ways)
o Paradox: how can a good state with a right to rule have that right if its subjects don’t have a general duty to comply with its directives?
o Raz’s response: distinguishes
♣ laws that address wrongs mala in se (morally wrong in themselves) – here one has a moral obligation not to do the wrong (ex. murder, steal) whether the laws says so or not. Where there are prudential reasons, then these are additional reasons but not moral ones.
♣ laws that address wrongs mala prohibita (depend for their wrongfulness on the fact that they have been made the subject of regulation) – the latter case serves coordination purposes, and for Raz, the fact that there is a law doesn’t create the obligation, it’s that the law works so that people do indeed coordinate their behaviour that creates the obligation (ex. you have an obligation not to pollute the river if everyone else refrains from polluting the river, but you wouldn’t if others were polluting the river, whether a law says you can’t or not). It’s the fact of social coordination itself that gives the moral reasons to join it.
*Green, ‘Legal Obligation and Authority’ in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Terminology:
Political obligation:
Legal obligation:
Command:
Political authority
- distinguished from (2 things)
Law
Non-voluntarist theory
Constitutive obligations
Instrumental justification
- example?
Necessity:
- Klosko?
- Finnis?
- Rawls?
Voluntarist theory
Consent:
- example?
Expressive obligation
Fairness
- propounded by?
NOTE: according to HT, Green treats Dworkin’s associative obligations theory unfairly and briefly.
Political obligation: the moral obligation to obey the law. Voluntarists think that this requires a voluntary subjection to law’s rule (eg. consent), while non-voluntarists think that the value of a just and effective legal system is in itself sufficient to validate law’s claims.
Legal obligation: legal requirements with which the law’s subjects are bound to perform that the law renders non-optional. It is different from compulsion, in that subjects can choose to break the law, but it is also different from a weighty reason to conform, because such is neither a sufficient (SC has no obligation not to reverse itself too often but it still has important reasons not to) nor necessary (there is an obligation not to tread on another’s lawn, but this is only a trivial reason) condition.
- NOTE: But are these really two examples of the condition being unnecessary rather than the first being insufficient? The first simply shows that the law is not the only weighty reason to act a certain way – the only difference between the two examples is that there is an obligation to do one and not the other, though this obligation doesn’t seem to play much of a role.
Command: According to Austin, command = an expression of will + an attached risk, however small, of suffering an evil for non-compliance. It accounts for the stringency of obligations: “When I am talking directly of the chance of incurring the evil … I employ the term duty, or … obligation”.
Political authority is a right to rule with a correlative duty to obey. Legal authority is a subcategory, but it is contrasted with theoretical authority, the authority held by experts, which doesn’t claim a right to obedience or even to be believed.
Law: to engage in a debate about whether there is an obligation to obey the law, we will describe the nature of law as 1) institutionalized (connected to courts, legislatures etc.), 2) of wide scope (governing a large, loosely structured and open-ended group) and 3) morally fallible. It is after adopting this definition that political obligation turns on the moral reasons to obey mandatory requirements of a wide-ranging, morally fallible, institutionalized authority.
Non-voluntarist theory: A theory is non-voluntarist if its principles justifying legal authority do not invoke the choice or will of the subjects among its reasons for thinking they are bound to obey.
Constitutive obligations: A non-voluntarist theory that argues against looking for moral justifications for a duty to obey because a political association, like membership in any group, is itself pregnant with obligations (Dworkin)
Instrumental justification: A non-voluntarist theory where law can be instrumentally justified because it helps subjects comply better with reasons that are relevant to them. Raz’s normal justification theory is an example.
Necessity: The law is justified when it helps people comply with reasons but only if it is restricted to the domain of necessary social functions. Philosophers disagree as to what is necessary: Klosko confines it to “presumptively beneficial public goods”, while Finnis allows self-evident values including life, knowledge, play and religion. Rawls would also allow just arrangements not yet established.
Voluntarist theory: Political authority depends on the voluntary subjection to law’s rule.
Consent: Political authority requires the consent of its subjects. Locke is a proponent, defining consent as including enjoyment of benefits of government.
Expressive obligations: we are bound to obey the law because it is an appropriate expression of gratitude, respect and sense of belonging to the community. Raz thinks that the same reason we owe obligations to our friends justifies obligations to the law.
Fairness: the most influential voluntarist argument, propounded by Hart and Raz: political obligation grounds in a willingness to benefit from a system of mutual restraint. If we benefit from others not breaking the law, we owe an obligation not to break it ourselves.
Notes
I. OBLIGATIONS IN THE LAW
i. How should the law be presented?
- Bentham (Kelsen)?
- Hart and Raz? (and where do they differ?)
- Honore and Dworkin?
- Bentham: “Every article of law has in common with the rest [in that it] commands and by doing so creates… obligations.” Therefore, Bentham and Kelsen think that the content of a legal system should be presented solely in terms of duty-imposing and duty-excepting laws, because it reveals the conditions under which the coercive power of law will be met
- Hart and Raz think that this presentation would be uninformative and unwieldy, but while Hart is concerned about it concealing the social functions of law, Raz thinks that it hides the different kinds of reasons for action that they create
- Honoré and Dworkin both devised theories that bypassed the issue [Does this show that it is meaningless, unimportant
Notes
I. OBLIGATIONS IN THE LAW
ii. What accounts for the stringency of legal obligations?
Content:
- Green?
- Green thinks that the content of legal obligations does not account for their stringency, because it is neither sufficient (high courts have no obligation not to reverse themselves too often but they still have important reasons not to) nor necessary (we have an obligation not to trample on other people’s lawns, but this is only a small reason) for someone to pursue a certain course of action.
[I think this doesn’t show that it is insufficient, only unnecessary – the first example only shows that there are other very weighty reasons and that a legal obligation is therefore unnecessary. Also, the law is usually couched in absolute terms: a law not to do something too often is simply unenforceable. The difference between law and other reasons is that the law’s demands are absolute (subject only to defences), while other reasons more readily give way to competing reasons.]
Notes
I. OBLIGATIONS IN THE LAW
ii. What accounts for the stringency of legal obligations?
Sanction:
- Austin & Kelsen? (where do they differ?)
- Command theory?
- Kelsen’s sanction theory?
- Austin and Kelsen both thought that sanction was behind legal obligations, though Austin envisaged a direct connection while Kelsen envisaged an indirect one
o Command theory: Austin defines command as an expression of will coupled with an attached risk, however small, of suffering an evil for non-compliance. This risk of sanction accounts for the stringency of obligations: “When I am talking directly of the chance of incurring the evil … I employ the term duty, or … obligation”.
o Kelsen’s sanction theory: Kelsen objects to the command theory and the content of a legal duty to be only part of a triggering condition for the mandatory norm which commands or authorizes officials to impose a sanction. “[A] norm: ‘You shall not murder’ is superfluous, if a norm is valid: ‘He who murders ought to be punished. [Thus,] legal obligation is not, or not immediately, the behavior that ought to be. Only the coercive act, functioning as a sanction, ought to be.”
Notes
I. OBLIGATIONS IN THE LAW
ii. What accounts for the stringency of legal obligations?
- Hart’s criticisms of the sanction theory:
- misrepresents …
- response - renders unintelligible…
- response - inadequate explanation of…
- response - reinforcing vs constituting duties
o Misrepresents a range of disparate legal consequences, including compensation and invalidation, as if they all function as penalties
♣ NOTE: Perhaps the terminology of ‘penalty’ is inapt, but the premises are still valid, in that the law operates to place an individual in a worse position for non-compliance than they would be if they complied. Maybe the goal of all law is not to punish, but the effect of all law on an individual is to make him want to comply because it would put him in a better position than non-compliance.
Also, if a power-conferring law really was unconnected with any notion of penalty, then why is it that trying to enforce an invalid contract put one in contempt of court? Power-conferring laws, in reality, limit what we can do, because law is based on the premise that everything that is not prohibited is lawful. Thus, without the law that wills must be signed, we are free to make wills however we want…
o Renders unintelligible duties in the absence of sanctions, eg. duty of high courts to apply the law
♣ NOTE: But it doesn’t – these duties are not legal duties but moral ones. The sanction theory merely does not address all types of duties. It is perfectly true of legal duties – duties that are attached to sanctions.
o Inadequate explanation of non-optionality: ‘you have an obligation not to murder’ cannot merely mean ‘if you murder you will be punished’, because the law is not indifferent between people murdering and being jailed, and not murdering at all. “The right to disobey the law is not obtainable by the payment of a penalty or a license fee” (Francome v Mirror Group Newspapers Ltd)
♣ NOTE: Is it though? Of course society and legislators might not be indifferent, but is the law really indifferent? In the same way as a shopkeeper is not indifferent between people paying £5 for a book and not buying a book at all (because he wants to sell books), surely the economy is indifferent as between the two: a book is worth £5 – it’s the same whether you have a book or £5 to buy it with.
o The normal function of sanctions is to reinforce duties not constitute them. Avoiding sanctions is not the only or, contrary to Holmes, primary reason for people being interested in knowing their duties. People want to be guided by their duties, and officials invoke them as reasons for and not merely consequences of their decisions.
Notes
I. OBLIGATIONS IN THE LAW
ii. What accounts for the stringency of legal obligations?
Hart’s rule-based theory
- what might sanctions mark?
- what must an obligation-imposing rule be?
- what does this account for if not their validity?
- when will obligations be valid?
- sanctions might mark circumstances in which people are obliged to conform, but they have an obligation only when subject to a practiced social rule. The fact that people use it as a rule makes it normative. An obligation-imposing rule must 1) be reinforced by serious or insistent pressure to conform, 2) they must be believed important to social life or some valued aspect of it, and 3) their requirements may conflict with the interests and goals of the subject.
o This accounts for the nature of obligations not their validity: obligations will only be 1) legally valid if part of a legal system as certified by the tests for law in that system, and 2) morally valid if supported by sound moral reasons
Notes
I. OBLIGATIONS IN THE LAW
ii. What accounts for the stringency of legal obligations?
Criticism of Hart’s rule-based theory
- people speak of obligations while aware that there are no relevant social practices (eg. lone vegetarian in a meat-eating society) and Hart’s conditions can be satisfied without obligation (eg. handing over a wallet to a mugger) (Dworkin 1978, 50-54; Raz 1990, 53-58)
Notes
I. OBLIGATIONS IN THE LAW
ii. What accounts for the stringency of legal obligations?
Reason-based theory
- obligations are content-independent reasons that are both categorical and pre-emptive in force – they do not depend on the nature or merits of the action that they require, but rather require the subject to set aside his own view of the merits and comply nonetheless: Raz, though foreshadowed by Hobbes and Locke
o Raz: obligations are categorical reasons that are protected by exclusionary reasons not to act on some (though not normally all) of the competing reasons to the contrary. Their stringency is accounted for by their insulating the required action from the general competition of reasons.
Notes
I. OBLIGATIONS IN THE LAW
ii. What accounts for the stringency of legal obligations?
Reception of reason-based theory
- Perry and Regan
- Marmor and Finnis
- Perry and Regan express doubts about whether it is ever reasonable to exclude entirely from consideration an otherwise valid reason, but the theory has been adopted in contrasting views of the nature of law: Finnis 1979, 231-59, Marmor 2001
Notes
II. AUTHORITY, OBLIGATION AND LEGITIMACY
Background:
Competition markets and mutual nuclear deterrence are not legal systems though people adjust their behavior in response to them. A social order is a legal system only if it has effective (de facto) authority, though this authority may not be justified.
Notes
II. AUTHORITY, OBLIGATION AND LEGITIMACY
i. What is legal authority and how is it related to obligations?
Authority is a claim to the right to obedience
- Wolff
- Weber
- Friedman
- Wolff: “To claim authority is to claim the right to be obeyed [and] obedience is not a matter of doing what someone tells you to do. It is a matter of doing what he tells you to do because he tells you to do it.” This is not true of all authority (eg. theoretical authority (experts) don’t claim obedience or even a right to be believed), but it is normally true for political authority (including legal authority). The right to be obeyed is not the same as to comply
o Weber: It is “as if the ruled had made the content of the command the maxim of their conduct for its very own sake”. The justification is content-independent.
- Friedman: “[I]f there is no way of telling whether an utterance is authoritative, except by evaluating its contents to see whether it deserves to be accepted in its own right, then the distinction between an authoritative utterance and advice or rational persuasion will have collapsed”.
Notes
II. AUTHORITY, OBLIGATION AND LEGITIMACY
i. What is legal authority and how is it related to obligations?
Sources thesis
- Raz
Criticisms:
- Waluchow
- Soper, Greenawalt, Edmundson
- Raz says that the test for the existence and content of law must be based only on social facts and not on moral arguments. Authority must “establish their existence and content in ways which do not depend on raising the very same issues which the authority is there to settle”. If the law is to settle moral issues, it cannot itself engage in the same debate.
- Criticism of the sources thesis:
o Waluchow: The law has other functions such as educating its subjects about right and wrong, and this is ill-served with the attitude that the rules are to be obeyed because they are rules
o Soper, Greenawalt, Edmundson: Legal authority involves no claim right, but only a set of liberties to decide certain questions for a society and enforce their decisions
Notes
II. AUTHORITY, OBLIGATION AND LEGITIMACY
i. What is legal authority and how is it related to obligations?
Liberty conception
- Legal authority is a set of liberties to decide certain questions for a society and enforce their decisions.
Notes
II. AUTHORITY, OBLIGATION AND LEGITIMACY
ii. Is the character of law’s authority a matter for descriptive or normative analysis?
Descriptive
Normative
- Free market (Hayek)
- Dworkin’s ‘more relaxed’ understanding
no notes
- we should understand law to claim only the sort of authority it would be justifiable for the law to have
o Free Market: Hayek: ‘The ideal type of law … provides merely additional information to be taken into account in the decision of the actor’. The nature of legal authority should be understood analogically to a free market.
o Dworkin’s ‘more relaxed’ understanding of legal authority: Dworkin thinks that the law is not trying to communicate guidance, but that a subject considering his legal duties is having a “conversation with oneself … trying to discover his own intention” in acting. Thus the law claims nothing independently of what each does well to regard it as claiming.
Notes
II. AUTHORITY, OBLIGATION AND LEGITIMACY
iii. What is the relationship between obligation and legitimacy?
Obligation
- Dworking
Legitimacy
- Rawls
- Kelsen
- Obligation:
Dworkin: “[T]hough obligation is not a sufficient condition for coercion, it is close to a necessary one. A state may have good grounds in some special circumstances for coercing those who have no duty to obey. But no general policy of upholding the law with steel could be justified if the law were not, in general, a source of genuine obligations” - Legitimacy:
o Rawls: “[A]cquiesence in, or even consent to, clearly unjust institutions does not give rise to obligations”. Thus legitimacy precedes an obligation to obedience.”
o Kelsen: A legal system that doesn’t justifiably coerce won’t be able to assure the law-abiding that others will obey – effectiveness is a necessary (though insufficient) condition for justified authority.
Notes
III. Obligations to the law
i. Do we owe an obligation to obey the law?
- Wolff’s dilemma
- objection to Wolff’s theory
(i) principled objection
(ii) practical point - better understanding of Wolff’s concern and response that this doubt is unfounded
- Law’s essential features are: (3 points_
- No obligation of obedience: Wolff’s dilemma: “If the individual retains his autonomy by reserving to himself in each instance the final decision whether to co-operate, he thereby denies the authority of the state; if, on the other hand, he submits to the state and accepts is claim to authority then … he loses his autonomy”. Wolff favours autonomy and thus defends anarchism, because he is uneasy about surrendering judgment – how can it be rational to act against reason as one see it?
- Objections to Wolff’s theory:
o A principled objection to every surrender of judgment is self-defeating, because a rational anarchist needs voluntary surrendering of judgment (eg. contracts) as a substitute for authoritative ordering (Soper)
o By surrendering judgment in some matters people can spend more time thinking about more important things, so a partial surrendering of judgment may enhance people’s autonomy overall - In the nature of law that there is an obligation to obey: A better understanding of Wolff’s concern is whether it is justifiable to surrender judgment wholesale to the law. Some say that this doubt is unfounded because it is of the nature of law that there is an obligation to obey it (Fuller, Finnis).
To surmount this difficulty we adopt a definition of law compatible with both views. Law’s essential features are: - Law is institutionalized: all law is connected to the activities of institutions (courts, legislatures, administration etc.)
- Legal systems have a wide scope: law is not limited to restricted groups (eg. families) or domains (eg. baseball). It governs the relationship between a large, loosely structured and open-ended group of strangers
- Law is morally fallible
In this way, political obligation turns on whether there are moral reasons to obey the mandatory requirements of a wide-ranging, morally fallible, institutionalized authority.
Notes
IV. Non-voluntarist theories
A theory is non-voluntarist if its principles justifying legal authority do not invoke the choice or will of the subjects among its reasons for thinking they are bound to obey.
Notes
IV.1. constitutive obligations (Dworkin)
ii. Is the character of law’s authority a matter for descriptive or normative analysis?
NOTE: This is a very brief and unfair treatment of Dworkin’s theory
- The very nature of a political society includes political obligation: Attempts to find independent moral justifications for obligation are mistaken and conceptually confused, because “political association, like family or friendship and other forms of association more local and intimate, is itself pregnant of obligation” (Dworkin).
o “We have not understood what itmeansto be a member of political society if we suppose that political obligation is something we might not have had and that therefore needs to bejustified” (McPherson)
- Objection: Indeed people in organic associations often feel obligations to other members but these obligations are usually justified on independent grounds, for example the value of obligations attached to social rules, and thus why duties bind has no general answer but depends on the roles and duties. Dworkin, meanwhile, believes there is such a general duty, as long as the members think that their obligations are special, personal and derive from a good faith interpretation of equal concern for the wellbeing of all members. But why is the ground of duty obedience and not (eg.) fraternity? This theory needs more argument.
Notes
IV. 2. Instrumental justification
- example
- 2 points about Raz’s theory
- Authority may be instrumentally justified as a way to help its subjects do what they ought: eg. Raz’s ‘normal justification thesis’, which states that authority is justified when it helps its subjects comply with reasons that apply to them better than they can on their own.
o Important points about Raz’s theory:
♣ It will not apply where it is more important for subjects to decide for themselves than the decide correctly
♣ It is not a utilitarian theory, because that would require more commitment as to what reasons are relevant
Notes
IV. 2. Instrumental justification
Criticism
- too braod and too narrow
o This does apply to theoretical authority (we obey doctors who know better than we do, but this is not blind deference because it is subject to higher-order considerations like whether the authority is trustworthy etc.), but does it really apply to political authority? Yes, to an extent: legislators may know better than most about certain subjects (eg. global warming) but scientists may know as well or better. Also, there are some areas where there are no criteria of relevant expertise at all.
o The theory is both too broad and too narrow:
♣ Broad: we don’t think that political authority should be acknowledged whenever the rulers can better ensure conformity to right reasons – there are matters inappropriate or too trivial for political regulation.
♣ Narrow: outside theoretical authority, it can only apply to integrate the activity of people who must cooperate but who disagree on the matters at hand. But it is unclear how much deference to authority is needed in this context: sometimes, providing information or restructuring incentives would suffice (Green)
V. Voluntarist theories
V.1. Consent
NOTE: Different versions of consent:
- Loche
- Green
- An original social contract – that people once upon a time united to under the same law: Locke
- People today have undertaken an obligation by some act that amounts to consent: Green
V. Voluntarist theories
V.1. Consent
What is consent?
- original social contract
- US declaration of independence
- Locke
- criticisms
(i) how is consent given?
- Finnis
- response
(ii) consent is irrelevant
(iii) there is no consent
- Plato
- Locke
- response?
What are we consenting to? To follow the law, or to suffer the sanctions if we don’t?
Past consent current habit BUT not current obligation? (Of the original social contract binding everyone subsequently living in the society and consenting for them, until these individuals opt out and withdraw that consent)
- Consent of the subjects is the justification for political authority
o Governments “derive their powers from the consent of the governed” (American Declaration of Independence)
o “Men being … by nature all free, equal, and independent, no one can be put out of this estate and subjected to the political power of another without his own consent.” Locke.
- Criticism:
o How is consent given? Voluntarists require the actual consent of each subject, but not to every law or application thereof. Finnis says that this is absurd: the very reason we need authority is to substitute for unanimity in co-ordination problems that involve everyone in the community.
♣ BUT consent theorists don’t apply consent to ‘coordination problems’ but rather to the establishment of a political community: the mere capacity of one to violently affect another’s interests is insufficient for them both to be subject to law (contrary to what Kant argues) – the two must agree to unite under one jurisdiction.
o Consent is irrelevant: Even in this confined form there is the question of whether it is in fact given and if so, whether it would bind. Consent is not just consensus: it is a performative commitment. But like all promises, there are limits to validity (eg. mistake, coercion, duress), and consent can be revoked. Therefore, a consent theory can only be of value if we can explain why we also value a power to bind ourselves to obey. Hume thinks that consent is redundant because any plausible answer to why we are bound by a promise would also account for our obligation to allegiance.
♣ BUT there can be non-promissory conditions on obedience:
• Power to give and withhold consent serves as a protective function
• Consent allows people to establish political allegiances by creating or joining political societies (eg. the Commonwealth)
• Consent also establishes the acceptability of government, and might signal that it has a good chance of being effective (which is itself a precondition for justification of political authority)
o Many people have done nothing that constitutes consent: Plato thinks that continued residence counts, and Locke extends this to enjoyment of benefits of government. But this cannot count as consent because often there are no feasible alternatives.
V. Voluntarist theories
V.2. Expressive Obligations
- We are bound to obey because that is an appropriate expression of gratitude (for all that the law gives us), respect (for good-faith efforts to guide us), and a sense of belonging to the community.
- Raz draws an analogy to friendship: we choose our friends, and as such owe obligations to them of loyalty. We also owe loyalty to the society to which we belong and with which we identify.
V. Voluntarist theories
V.3. Fairness
- difficulties with benefits (3 give)
- compare gratitude
- what is the most influential voluntarist argument?
Difficulties:
- Are we actually benefited?
- If we are benefited, did we ask for the benefit?
- Is the benefit connected in any meaningful way to the burden? (Contrast to estoppel and mutual benefit and burden doctrine)
Compare gratitude – connected to goodwill and emotions etc. (affective aspect)
- Most influential voluntarist argument: political obligation grounds in a bare willingness to benefit from a system of mutual restraint (Hart, Rawls). Those who accept the benefits of a fair scheme of cooperation have a duty to do their allotted part under the scheme.