Rule of Law Flashcards
Marmor
Countries that cherish the rule of law and those who are critical of it
Countries in which it has been neglected for many years i.e. Easter European countries like Romania
Marxists are critical of the rule of law
Marmor
Common mistake about the rule of law
to confuse it with the ideal of the rule of good law, i.e. respect for freedom and dignity.
Seems Hayek fell into this trap
Marmor
what does the rule of law become when it regarded as a general ideal of good law?
no-longer a unique ideal but a whole philosophy about what the law should achieve and the values it should uphold
Marmor
what is the challenge?
defining legalism per se, a much narrower concept, and explaining why it is good and to what extent
He thinks like his grandma’s jam, too much of the rule of law is a bad thing
Marmor
what does he assume the essence of the rule of law is?
what 2 components are there?
- requires that governments, namely de facto political authorities, should rule (i.e. guide their subjects’ conduct)
- requires that the law by which governments purport to rule should be such that it can actually guide human conduct
- the second has attracted more scholarly discussion (‘and rightly so’
Marmor
principle 1. governments should rule by law
‘government by law, not by men.’
shows how this is misleading because (1) legislators etc are men, (2) there are sometimes there are legally ultra vires actions (where government purports to be authorised by a specific act but is in fact not)
Marmor
principle 1. governments should rule by law
what does it mean that governments ought to rule by law?
We can only answer this if have an idea about what would violate this ideal: how could a government rule if not by law?
Depends on a theory about what law is, and what kinds of means of social control are legal.
E.g. command theory of the law - order back by sanction of the de facto sovereign would be law, by definition (Austin). But difficult to imagine it being sustained by means which are not legal.
At the other end of the spectrum (natural law), where only those norms that meet a certain moral constraint count as law, a great deal of what we would call law would not really be law even in a well ordered society..
the two horns of the dilemma
Marmor
how does principle 1 relate to principle 2?
The idea that governments should rule by law must be premised on the assumption that rule by law, regardless of law’s specific content is to be preferred to governance by other means of social control
- brings us onto principle 2 - law must be such that it actually can guide human conduct
Marmor
The law should be such that it can actually guide human conduct
the conditions:
certain conditions that the law has to meet in order to be able to fulfil its pivotal function of guiding human conduct
Consensus on what these conditions are, following roughly the list of Fuller:
- generality
(cannot be addressed to individuals) - promulgation
(one must be aware of the rules if they are to be guided by them) - no retroactive rules
(must prescribe behaviour prospectively) - clarity
(cannot follow unclear prescriptions) - no contradictory rules
(people can not follow both competing prescriptions) - no impossible prescriptions
(a rule that cannot be followed cannot guide human conduct) - stability
(law can change but not too frequently since many of our actions which the law purports to regulate require advance planning, preparation and a certain guaranteed expectations about the future normative environment) - consistent application
(requires independent judiciary, relatively easy to access litigation and reliable enforcement agencies)
Marmor
why is it a virtue for the law to have these attributes, if it must have them in order to fulfil its function?
- if feature x is functionally good for A to fulfil designated task y, them having x is functionally good for A - i.e. extent to which a knife is made to cut, then the sharpness of the knife is functionally good; a sharp knife is a good knife - same for the rule of law
- the better is scores in one the better it functions in regulating behaviour
Marmor
Why might the rule of law virtues, though essentially functional, promote other goods?
condition of generality may ensure a certain level of impartiality which we value in addition to the fact that it enables the law to function as a social instrument of social control
condition of promulgation and publicity render it politically transparent and open for public deliberation, which we may value independently of law’s ability to guide conduct
This explains why many view the rule of law as an important ideal - upholding the rule of law is likely to promote a whole set of goods that are worth promoting.
Marmor
Marmor challenges the analogy of law fulfilling the conditions of law more to a sharper knife (being a better knife)
not necessarily the case that more of a good thing, the better
‘promoting one kind of good often comes at the expense of another.’
‘less trivially, however, there are some values or ideals that do not call, on their own grounds, for anything like full or perfect implementation… this is because such values on their own grounds set only a rough standard whereby gross deviations from it would be wrong.’
Marmor on generality
norm-subject
In other words, the generality-
relevance principle imposes a certain reason-based identification of the norm-subjects which is essentially general in nature, thus
preventing partiality and favoritism of a certain kind. But of course, there are endless possibilities for the law to be biased, prejudiced,
or unjustly discriminate between groups of people, even if it strictly adheres to the generality-relevance principle. Apartheid in South
Africa was quite legalistic in this respect. If the law is based on bad reasons, then the fact that its norm-subjects are identified on the
basis of those reasons does not prevent it from being bad law
Marmor on generality
norm-act
a matter of degree
it must be distinguished from vagueness
notes that generality can be fleshed out by other agencies, i.e. the court when it interprets a statute
rule of law requires that the law be such that it can actually guide human conduct, it is indifferent about the question of who makes the law
Marmor on generality
promulgation
The law is a system of norms, and norms purport to provide reasons for action, so it must be publicized to those whose action it purports to guide. But, as we have seen, such a functional explanation does not fully capture the values we associate with the requirement of promulgation.
From a purely functional
perspective, many laws need not be made entirely public.
To the extent that we have reasons to require a wider promulgation of the law, those reasons must be derived from other, non-functional
values, such as the need for public scrutiny, open
deliberation, and critical appraisal of the laws of our community. In other words, the
promulgation of law serves deliberative and critical values over and beyond its role in securing the normative efficiency of the law.
On the other hand, it should not be assumed that promulgation is always
morally costless. Under certain circumstances, it is better if people are not entirely aware of the laws governing their situation. There is, in such cases, a certain conflict between the political values of
promulgation, ensuring public scrutiny and critical appraisal, and considerations of individual justice or human compassion. From a political perspective perhaps we would always want to put the law
under glaring light, but there is something to be said for the need to resolve some subtleties if not quite in the darkness, at least in the twilight
Marmor on generality
no retroactive rules
Judicial decisions, then, must be acknowledged as introducing legal changes which often have, at least with respect to the particular
litigants, retroactive effect. Most judges and jurists are quite aware of that, and some of them believe that this in itself is sufficient to
warrant a policy of judicial restraint and conservativism, requiring judges to refrain from changing the law. Introducing legal changes is always better left to the legislature, they say, since the latter can do
so prospectively with due warning.
Although the concern about retroactivity is a serious one, the conclusion is far too quick, even from the limited perspective of the rule of law virtues. After all, flexibility in the application of the law is partly what makes the law
an effective tool of social control. The sheer number and complexity of legal issues in a modern society renders it impossible for any legislature to deal with all the subtleties and legal ramifications
of the entire normative system. A modern legal system must rely on other agents, like judges and administrative agencies, to work out these numerous details and adjust the law to specific cases and
changing circumstances. Presumably, much more harm will be done by a legal system that does not allow for such flexibility in the application of the law than the harm in retroactivity which could be avoid
Marmor on generality
no retroactive rules - on Dworkin
Dworkin distinguishes between policy and principle
Policy is based on societal goals, whereas principle is based on pre-existing rights.
As long as judges refrain from policy decisions then they would not violate the requirement to avoid retroactivity, because their decisions would simply re-affirm pre-existing rights: ‘if the plaintiff has a right against the defendant, then the defendant has a corresponding duty, and it is that duty, not some new duty created by the court, that justifies the award against him.’
But Marmor says that this is illusory… e.g. case law on product liable Donoghue v Stevenson arguably driven by policy as well as better protecting the rights of relevant parties!
Marmor
Clarity of rules
we should also bear in mind that the law is often obscure not because the legislators (or other law makers) have made a mistake in its drafting. In a pluralistic, democratic society,
legislation is often a result of a delicate compromise between
conflicting views and purposes. Sometimes the only way to achieve a compromise is by forgoing maximum clarity. Parties to a dispute may find it easier to agree on a formula which is not entirely clear,
hoping (as they often do without too much delusion) that future interpretation will favor their stance. If we could envisage a world in which no level of obscurity in law making is allowed, we might find that world to be one in which the only law enacted is the law
supported by a solid ruling majority. A ‘winner takes all’ strategy, as this would entail, is a high price to pay for the advantages of maximum clarity.
Whether one thinks that the need to compromise in a pluralistic society is a regrettable fact obviously depends on one’s moral-political views about the values of pluralism. I cannot go into this here. Suffice it to say that for those who regard pluralism itself as a virtue, the need to compromise is not necessarily a regrettable fact. To the extent that a certain level of unclarity tends to facilitate desirable compromises, maximum clarity may not always be the objective that we ought to seek.
E.g. the aims of the land register - clear goal of ‘complete and accurate’ register to promote the indefeasibility of the register; however, this would prioritise the rights of purchasers at the expense of those in actual occupation who through no fault of their own, have had their home sold (Boland)
Marmor
No contradiction
integrity basically entails a ‘winner takes all strategy’ which is at odds with value pluralism. The whole point
of respect for value pluralism is that we do not want to have a legal-political system whereby the winner (be it the ruling majority or the view of the supreme court) imposes its comprehensive moral views
on the rest of the population.
A certain moral fragmentation and incoherence is inescapable if we are to respect pluralism as such (indeed the minority view in any supreme court can provide authority for future rulings!)
Once again, it is all a matter of degree; law cannot function if it is too fragmented and morally incoherent. But coherence comes at a price, and sometimes the price
Marmor
No impossible prescription
Furthermore, not infrequently the law is justified in setting standards of conduct which may be somewhat unrealistically high. The
law may have, in certain areas, a symbolic or educational function which permits it to set higher standards than those that some of its subjects could comply with. For example, it is arguable that in societies which have a disturbing history of racial discrimination, we should expect the law to impose very strict, even harsh, anti-discrimination laws that in other societies might not be warranted.
There is in such cases a symbolic and educational value to setting standards so high, given the past iniquities and their potentially lingering effects. Needless to say, the higher the law sets its standards, the more it runs the risk of noncompliance and failing to guide conduct.
But perhaps the risk of a certain functional failure in the law is sometimes a reasonable price to pay for such symbolic and educational objectives
i.e. discrimination laws, environment law which force countries to cut their emissions by perhaps unattainable levers or technology forcing laws which compel industries to invest for the purposes of developing new technology
Marmor
Stability over a
The desirable level of the stability of the law over time is a very rough standard. We know that the law must change
over time, and we also know that it would be difficult to follow the law if it changes too frequently. But it would be absurd to assume that we can have a precise notion of the ideal pace of change. This
requirement of the rule of law is basically a rough standard, whereby gross deviations from it, in both directions, constitute a deficiency. We can criticize changes in the law if they are too frequent or too
slow. But it hardly makes any sense to say that a given change in the law is ever so slightly too fast, or just a little bit too slow. A rough
standard of stability over time is what law needs to apply in order to function properly
Marmor
Congruence between the rules and their application
Dan-Cohen argues, and I think rightly so, that some discrepancy between the content of the rules addressed to the public and those
addressed to officials is not always regrettable. On the contrary, it enables the law, particularly in the criminal domain, to accommodate conflicting purposes. For example, the law may instruct
judges and other officials to interpret various offences in a very technical and rather restrictive manner, thus making sure that only
behavior which is surely and unquestionably wrong would be subject to punishment. At the same time, however, the law would achieve better deterrent effect, and perhaps, on the whole, better social results, if the general public’s perception of such offenses is more expansive. After all, the good citizen who wants to be guided by the law would want to be on the safe side, avoiding behavior which is on the verge of illegality. But again, in case the citizen
happens to stumble and finds himself in front of a court, the judge should also play it safe and convict the defendant only if she is very confident that the conduct was, indeed, legally wrong. Thus, the fact
that the rules are understood somewhat differently by the public and the judges enables both to be on the safe side
But, Marmor raises a complexity:
Consider a non-criminal case first: suppose we assume that similar considerations apply to contract law as well. Suppose that it would be better if people believed that their
contractual obligations are somewhat stricter than the technical-legal doctrines actually require. The problem with such a situation
is rather apparent here: the more there is a discrepancy between general perceptions and legal technicalities, the greater the relative advantage of those parties with better access to legal expertise, who are, most often, the wealthier parties or the repeat-players.
This raises concerns about equality - a systemic lack of congruence between general perception of the law and its actual application to specific cases normally plays into the hands of those who can afford better access to legal expertise
Thus, the social advantage of the incongruence between the rules which are addressed to the public and officials must be weighed against the potential inequality
Marmor
The inner morality of the law?
Fuller
Fuller has argued that these conditions exhibit the inner morality of the law - i.e. conditions the law must meet regardless of its content
Marmor
The inner morality of the law?
Hart and Raz
Marmor’s claim
They responded to these virtues of the rule of law as of merely functional (means of social control) and not moral values
But, marmor claims that his discussion of the values shows that they are also moral-political virtues - they enhance certain goods which we have reasons to value in addition to their functional merit