Standing Flashcards
Schiemann (1990) on restriction on standing
wherever standing rules restrict someone from pursuing a claim, the law “regards it as preferable that an illegality should continue rather than the person excluded should have access to the courts.”
Senior Court Act 1981, s31(3):
High Court must approve applications for JR and it will not do so unless “the applicant has a sufficient interest in the matter to which the application relates.”
The issue is how we define sufficient interest. Term itself is illusory and doesn’t give much guidance and Elliott suggests that it’s just a short hand way of saying the court itself is to decide the test.
Miles draws a useful distinction between private rights and public wrongs:
• Narrow (private rights) model (or ‘closed’ as Schiemann describes): standing operates only to protect individuals where their material interests have been affected. Individualistic model
• Broad (public wrongs) model (or ‘open’ as Schiemann describes): standing operates to protect the public interest against public wrongs. Communitarian model.
What does Feldman argue the approach depends on?
depends on identifying a constitutional ethic: i.e. what should JR do?
“Under a liberal political theory, oriented towards personal autonomy, individual rights and freedom of choice, litigation to protect individual material interests would certainly be regarded as legitimate, while attempts to represent public or ideological concerns, or the interests of future members of the political community, would be problematic. Civic republicans or communitarians would be much more likely to regard the latter type of interest group litigation as politically legitimate, and might consider the former type to be an illegitimate attempt to distort public interest decision making”.
So in determining the rules of standing
the judge will need to decide what sort of participation or representation in politics is required by the constitutional scheme
In other words, the judge will need to derive a ‘constitutional ethic’:
“The need for a judge to interpret the constitution in the light of society’s political arrangements and its dominant ideology emphasises the political nature of constitutional adjudication, and the link between constitutional and political legitimacy
Craig on the consequences of lacking such a constitutional ethic
Locus standi has given rise to case law which is complex and often conflicting. It will continue to be so until the courts develop a clearer ideaas to what they believe the purposes to be served by standingactually are.
Given the absence of parliamentary guidelines, it seems to be desirable that academics, Bar and Bench should help in the building of guidelines by identifying what are submitted to be or are regarded as relevant considerations and the order of priorities upon which that judgment is based…. If learned writers and Bar and Bench try to formulate what social purpose is sought to be achieved in the exercise of a discretion to accord standing or to grant leave, then in time clear principles should emerge with the aid of the appellate courts and academic writers; and if Parliament does not like them, then Parliament can change them.
But maybe some of the confusion in this process arises because the process itself, according to Feldman, is not all one-way but is, on the contrary, symbiotic. The cases which are heard as a result will themselves form and alter the prevailing ‘constitutional ethic’:
interest group litigation often represents a contribution to debate about political theory, by challenging prevailing ideas of constitutional or political legitimacy. Society’s response is shaped by its political and constitutional ethics, which may in turn be reshaped by the demands themselves
In particular, Feldman identifies four factors which may make up part of the ‘constitutional ethic’ which determines whether the rules of standing will be wide or narrow:
- Democracy and ethics, e.g. in the UK courts are often criticised for being ‘undemocratic’ when they adjudicate on public law issues, cf the exchange between the AG and Lord Bingham in the Belmarsh case, X, [2004] UKHL 56 para 42.
- Federalism; the existence of a federal structure means the courts can be called upon to adjudicate particular substantive issues because they raise questions of state or federal competence. See, e.g. issues relating to devolution in the UK, or relating to EU v UK competence.
- Ideological interests and the political community, in particular policy directives contained in constitutions. If courts accept even a limited jurisdiction to enforce these principles, Feldman argues that this inevitably extends the capacity for public interest litigation.
- The perceived proper role of the courts in protecting certain rights even when they are not contained in the constitution, e.g. the UK outside and before the HRA.
Schiemann on SCA and how that might inform our determination of the constitutional ethic
Schiemann thinks that, in deciding, it’s important to consider Parliament’s intention in enacting the SCA.
Aims of standing rules:
- Efficiency: courts must reduce time / costs of administrative system. Diplock: Fleet Street Casuals (IRC): rules prevent court’s time being wasted by busybodies with misguided / trivial complaints.
- Justice for applicants: desire to ensure those with a valid application are not denied justice. Diplock in IRC: rules which are too strict would create a ‘lacuna’ in the PL system. Claims from pressure groups etc. allow “the court to vindicate the rule of law and get the unlawful conduct stopped.
• Accountability of public authorities: Schiemann: social merit in having answerable DMs. This is reflected in the move toward a ‘public wrongs’ model.
o Originally it was only the AG who represented the ‘public interest’ before the courts. Number of 20th Century cases have liberalised this position. Harlow & Rawlings: this was because restrictive standing rules contradicted the idea of general judicial responsibility to control abuse of power. Basis for a claim was broadened with the 1981 Act and IRC and we now have representational standing where pressure groups can bring JR on public interest concerns.
♣ Greenpeace: G had standing to challenge Nuclear energy testing because it represented local interest and general public interest in preventing radioactive pollution).
♣ Rees-Mogg: Lord RM was allowed to challenge government decision to ratify Maastricht treaty due to concern with constitutional issues.
Move towards a public wrongs model
before Fleet Street Casuals standing ensured that individual rights, but not broader interests, could be asserted before the courts —it operated restrictively / inconsistently, dependent on the remedy sought.
• Fleet Street Casuals [1982]: case concerned an agreement between the IRC and Unions representing casual workers in Fleet Street (who hadn’t been paying taxes). National Federation argued that the deal was UV. HL: NF had no standing —it was merely a body of taxpayers without sufficient interest.
o Significant that the court made clear that standing would play a minimal role to keep out ‘abuse by busybodies, cranks, and other mischief-makers’ (Scarman).
o In a case like this, NF may have standing where there was illegality of ‘sufficient gravity’.
o Standing will play a role at the merits stage (Roskill and Wilberforce): suggests a two stage test: (i) at the permission stage courts will deny meddlesome Cs; (ii) when determined on the merits, case may show that C does not have sufficient interest (need to look at whole context).
♣ Elliott: questions whether re-opening standing at the permission stage may not be compatible with the Act; but is now standard practice — Rose Theatre Trust.
♣ Williams: doesn’t like the two-stage test: conflates standing with other issues, including merits and seems to indicate that standing does no real work at all (if all we’re interested in is the public wrong, no individual interest is required). Also doesn’t follow the legislation.
♣ Wade & Forsyth: problem is the point of standing is a good case on the merits may fail on standing: “it would seem to virtually abolishing the requirement of standing.”
Diplock notes parliamentary accountability: thus, here, the deal will be reviewable by Parl.
What does Cane argue re the courts stopping short of a strong ‘public wrongs’ moel?
court stops short of a strong ‘public wrongs’ model (standing depends only on justiciability of issues involved) and still requires them, despite effectively abolishing standing as a filter, to distinguish between different degrees of interest. This is the ‘worst of all possible worlds’
What two arguments does Endicott make?
• Although the question of merits is now raised before standing is decided, it is a mistake to think the issue of standing collapses into the wider question of substantive merit.:
o Merits relevant to standing in two ways: (i) no one has standing to proceed with a claim which clearly has no merit —this is not specific to JR; (ii) court needs to decide what the matter is in order to decide whether C has an interest ‘in the matter’ —e.g. in Fleet Street, C would have had standing if ‘the matter’ was something outrageous.
o Standing is still prior to the merits in that a case with no merit will be allowed to proceed if C has a sufficient interest and the court cannot yet see that the claim has no merit.
• Why not embrace a full public wrongs model? Point of making something unlawful is not to turn the judges into a general governments mistake department. Processes “need a justification of their own.”
o Rule of law may not require a legal response to unlawful conduct: RL requires that officials abide by the law, but when they don’t the RL requires the operation of a process for interfering only when that process itself will improve conformity to the law —either by changing official conduct for the future, or by remedying the unlawful results of a particular action. No grave lacuna because unlawful conduct does not come before a court.
♣ SR: real point is we don’t need a judicial response every time the law hasn’t been followed. Further, point that RL demands government by the law, indicates we need some control.
IRC applied inconsistently:
Although IRC was seen in ex. p. Smedley [1985] as having “greatly relaxed the rules as to locus standing” and allowed a single taxpayer to challenge the legality of a Treasury expenditure decision (where the issue was of general importance). It was interpreted restrictively here:
• Rose Theatre [1990]: Schiemann J accepted that direct financial or legal interest was not necessary for standing, but an applicant must demonstrate an interest beyond that of an ordinary citizen. If this were not the case, the phrase ‘sufficient interest’ would lose all meaning.
o Further, he thought that where several people without such an interest band together (as here) it would be absurd if they gained standing merely by “incorporating themselves into a company.”
o Useful to look at statute in determining whether an applicant has a right to challenge a given duty.
what is Elliott’s comment on Schiemann in Re Rose Theatre?
Schiemann appears to accept the possibility of associational standing, but thinks it’s not the case here, since those being represented didn’t have sufficient interest —he assumes that a sufficient interest can only be established by demonstrating some sort of personal stake in the decision. But this overlooks the possibility that sufficient interest may instead be established by demonstrating the importance of the matter means the litigation is in the public interest. Judges in Greenpeace and Dixon declined to follow the judgment. Sedley J questioned its soundness in part in Dixon and the liberal approach seems to have prevailed.
How does Cane criticise Shiemann’s decision?
• Misunderstands purpose: Schiemann thought function of standing rules is to prevent ‘uncertainty and chaos’ from resulting (e.g. to prevent a decision to build a motorway being challenged after it had been built). However, this has nothing to do with standing (per Cane) rather it’s time limits, other procedural rules, and residue discretion not to order a remedy that prevents such challenges.
• Rejects Schiemann’s argument that Cs with no standing can’t gain standing by incorporating: again misses the point: trust / company shouldn’t only be given standing where members have sufficient interest, rather the liberalisation of standing rules requires standing is given to “genuine representatives of interested persons.” “Representative standing is an important feature of any system of public law which is chiefly concerned to ensure that governments act lawfully” and helps ensure that poor / underprivileged persons’ interests are represented. Issues if such claims can only be brought by the AG because then the government is responsible for bringing the government to account
o Also, if we take Schiemann’s view, then CPAG was wrongly decided.
Personal note on Rose Theatre
Note: Schiemann thought a C must have “a greater right or expectation than any other citizen to have a decision taken lawfully.” However, other cases on campaign litigation have mentioned no such requirement (indeed almost the reverse). Instead of requiring any special interest, they have welcomed pressure group litigation where, as in WDM, it is unlikely someone else could make a challenge.
The case appears anomalous and appears to have been superseded by Walton —Sedley J in Dixon interpreted it narrowly as meriting a narrow approach under that specific statute, rather than dissenting from broader, more liberal, proposition in Fleet Street.
General liberalising trend
ex p Child Poverty Action Group [1990]: Woolf LJ discussed
standing of the pressure group: “the issues raised are agreed to be important in the field of social welfare and not ones which individual Cs for supplementary benefit could be expected to raise.” Further, CPAG play a prominent role in “giving advice, guidance, and assistance to such Cs.”
o Elliott: can see in Woolf’s judgment the desirability of permitting claims to be brought on behalf of disenfranchised. But note that the issue was not confronted directly.
o Cane: Public interest standing rather than associational standing: it’s not associational standing because the people CPAG purports to represent are not members of the organisation. However, “there is no reason why it should not… act as a representative of the public interest in areas in which it has expertise.” His argument is that we should recognise public interest standing.
General liberalising trend
ex. p. Rees-Mogg [1994]:
challenge to the ratification of the Maastricht treaty on grounds of constitutional legitimacy CA: refused application of JR (no jurisdiction to review signing of treaties) but accept RM has standing. Generous standing to RM is justified because it will promote the rule of law where: (i) there is a significant public interest at stake; and (ii) the DM’s action was a fragrant abuse of power.
o Note: is this really enough? It’s hard to see who could be a busybody if neither Greenpeace nor Rees-Mogg is. Perhaps someone with an “insincere interest” in the outcome?
o Justice / Public Law Project paper: This is different to the other cases, in that it was brought by an individual on no other basis than his “sincere concern for constitutional issues.” But the decision to allow the case to proceed is “testament to the courts having adopted a more liberal approach to who brings cases raising important public interest considerations.”
General liberalising trend
ex p Greenpeace (no. 2) [1994]:
G challenged permission for nuclear fuel testing. Otton J: allowed GP standing on the basis that interest groups won’t automatically be afforded standing because members were concerned about a particular basis, rather it will be decided on a “case by case basis”
o Based on the following factors: (i) 2500 members of G lived locally and had concerns about health issues; (ii) if denied standing, those G represented, might not have an effective way to bring issues before the court; (iii) such people do not have the same expertise, so even if they could bring the issue to the courts, the case would be less well-informed; (iv) expertise facilitates efficient use of court’s resources.
o Also mentioned, elsewhere in judgment, it was significant that their interest was part of a general public campaign.
o Comment on GP:
♣ Cane: reasoning was confusing but proper interpretation of the case is that GP was accorded standing as a representative of the public interest, not associational standing on the basis that its members were effected.
♣ Endicott:
• Otton’s reliance on GP’s affected members in Cumbria seems to be a red herring, as it neglects the true nature of GP —it’s not a Cumbrain health and safety organistation, but a global environmental campaign organization. The representative role of the pressure group should have been no more relevant than it was in WDM. However, given Otton J’s judgment, this case is only tentative support for public interest standing.
• Expertise of applicant: the danger in this criterion is that: (i) judges may not be able to make good decisions about quality / expertise of pressure group; (ii) it may discriminate against the underprivileged. Further, not sure why it’s relevant for associational standing where a democratic stake in the issue has been established, and for public interest standing, surely the case is still in the public interest regardless of expertise.
• However, notes that these dangers haven’t come to pass because the courts have been generous in granting standing.
General liberalising trend
Equal Opportunities Commission [1994]:
HL: recognised standing for EOC’s challenge to an employment statute on grounds of discrimination. Lord Keith: significant that the proceedings raise questions which are of public importance and affect a large section of the population.
o EOC had joined a worker to the proceedings (Mrs. Day) who did not have standing because she was asserting a personal interest in not being the victim of discrimination and therefore had a private law claim which she could bring before a tribunal.
Leading case ex p World Development Movement [1994]:
challenge to the government’s funding of the Pergau Dam in Malaysia. Rose LJ: WDB have standing. The merits of the challenge were an important, if not dominant, factor when considering standing and there were significant factors pointing to the conclusion that the Cs had sufficient interest within s.31(3).
“The real question is whether the applicant can show some substantial default or abuse, and not whether his personal rights or interests are involved.”
Important factors in allowing standing: (i) importance of vindicating the Rule of Law and Diplock’s lacuna concern in IRC; (ii) importance of the issue to the public; (iii) likely absence of any responsible challenger; (iv) prominent role of the applicants.
Analysis of WDM
Justice: although the organisation didn’t claim to represent a client group, the court accepted that in view of its reputation and track record, WDM had an interest in ensuring that aid money is lawfully spent. Important that, without WDM, there would likely be no other challenger.
Elliott: decision unequivocally recognizes that standing may be conferred upon a claimant because it is in the public interest that a matter is adjudicated before courts. Court draws a connection between importance of the issue and standing —this builds on contextual, public interest approach in IRC.
Miles (2000) argues that we need a democratic nexus —the autonomy of victims of maladministration requires that they should be able to choose whether the matter is litigated.
• However, this should be set against the competing view that there is a general interest in good administration, which may be threatened if representative Cs are barred from litigating where victims are unwilling to do so.
• EP: Miles argument does, perhaps, tell us that we shouldn’t allow pressure groups to bring cases where the victim is one C, who may not want details of their affairs in the courts. But in such situations the case for pressure group representation is weak anyway. And the law reflects this (Bulger).
Endicott:
• Rose LJ’s factors tell us what factors the court will look for beyond that C ‘finds the case interesting’. Rule of law doesn’t generally demand judicial process as a response to unlawful conduct, so we can boil down the relevant factors to: (i) importance of issues to the public; (ii) absence of any other likely challenger; (iii) expertise in the field. Only the third of these has anything to do with C’s interest in the matter, the other two are simply reasons why it may be a good idea to allow campaign litigation. These considerations may lead the court to think that they should treat C as though he has an interest, even though a groups interest is not at stake.
• Notable that the court in WDM did not assess its agenda to decide whether it was in the public interest. This seems to be a common feature of such litigation. However, Endicott argues this is not that important as any specific agenda will be countered in argument by the government contesting argument in court and the true public interest is in having the case heard.
• Campaign litigation does create a danger that argument in court will become a substitute for the political debates that ought to be conducted in Parliament —indeed, that’s often what C is seeking to achieve in bringing such actions (e.g. Rees Mogg). Endicott thinks it’s reasonable to limit standing in such cases, but the courts do this through: (i) requirement of an arguable case; (ii) limited grounds of JR.
Case law after WDM
ex. p. Dixon [1998]:
Dixon (local councilor) challenged planning permission for a quarry. Sedley J: Standing at the permission stage should only be denied if C is a ‘busybody’ —Dixon isn’t and is entitled as a citizen to draw the attention of the court to perceived illegality. Despite Rose Theatre, there is no requirement of a “special private interest in the subject matter” at the permission stage, although private interest will be an issue at the substantive hearing. He thinks the court’s only concern is to ensure “it is not being done for an ill motive.” Public law is not about rights —it is about wrongs, misuses of public power.
o Endicott: doors are now just about open in campaign litigation cases, however, groups must still show: (i) a prominent role in the issues (this distinguishes Greenpeace from Rose Theatre); (ii) if there is some particular potential C who is specially affected, the court will not be prepared to hear a claim from anyone else (Bulger); (iii) busybodies —person with no reasonable concern for the issues —do not have sufficient interest.
Case law after WDM
Bulger [2001]:
Father of B sought to challenge SS’s sentence of murderers. Rose LJ: denies standing. Wide standing is justified by RL and accountability of DMs, preventing private rights being denied by public bodies. However, parties to criminal proceedings and the Crown are able to challenge sentencing decisions.
Elliott: preventing other challenges where an individual has clear interest is the ‘flip side’ of WDM(allow group standing where non one individually is affected enough to bring a challenge) — RL is already protected because the Crown can bring a challenge.
Case law after WDM
Al-Haq [2009]:
foreign NGO sought to challenge government’s facilitation of weapons supply to Israel. Issues raised were non-justiciable and there was no standing. Cranston J: recognizes that the courts apply a liberal standing test to responsible, expert groups. However, he rejects C’s argument that standing must necessarily follow if there was a justiciable issue of public law for two reasons: (i) on principle, if an act affects a particular individual / group and they choose not to challenge it the courts must generally refuse to permit someone more remote from doing so; (ii) as a practical matter, it can’t be right that any NGO around the world has standing to bring a claim in similar circs.
Harlow (2002): decision is justified — although there is a public interest in just international policy, there is no public interest in making the courts into a forum for advocacy groups to attempt to force judicial influence of government policy
Case law after WDM
Walton [2010]:
• W (chairman of Road Sense, local opposition group) challenges construction of Aberdeen bypass. SC: reject W’s challenge based on substance, but thought he had standing.
o Lord Reed: Support for for the public wrongs/ RoL approach: SC clarified approach to standing in AXA and “intended to put an end to an unduly restrictive approach which had too often obstructed the proper administration of justice: an approach which presupposed that the only function of the court’s supervisory jurisdiction was to redress individual grievances, and ignored its constitutional function of maintaining the rule of law” Although it’s not the case that every person can challenge every potential breach by a public body, there may be cases where any individual, as a citizen, will have an interest. Rule of law wouldn’t be maintained if non-one could challenge an unlawful act because everyone was equally affected by it.
o Carnwath on remedies: interest of the applicant isn’t just a threshold requirement that ceases to be relevant once standing is established —it may be important regarding remedies. The liberalisation of standing means discretion as to remedies should act as a counterbalance. Thus, in this case, W wouldn’t get a remedy if his case succeeded; exercise of remedial discretion depends on factual / statutory context —here, countervailing public and private interests would be taken into account.
ADDITIONAL ACADEMIC LITERATURE ON STANDING
Schiemann:
We need to think about Parliament’s purposes in imposing a judicial duty to examine standing of litigants.
• Too restrictive standing rules will strip laws of their purpose: “unenforceable laws are delusions which can give rise to substantial anger and justifiable frustrations.”
• Advantages of an open system: (i) facilitation of justice —i.e. to prevent Diplock’s lacuna in IRC; (ii) to ensure public accountability in the admin system —courts won’t act unless set in motion by an applicant, so we need standing to ensure people can apply; (iii) incentivise better administration —prompt administrators to act with greater care.
• Advantages of a closed system I: (i) being sued is a distraction from the business of governing; (ii) threat of judicial action makes administrators focus on the wrong things —i.e. making decisions ‘judge proof’; (iii) financial costs, which are borne by the public purse; (iv) suspending decisions, while under review, which may need to be implemented quickly; (v) greater waiting time for genuine cases if the court is turned into a platform for spurious ones.
o Williams: these points are not really about standing, but rather can be dealt with via justiciability, time limits and reforms to the admin court system.
• Advantages of a closed system II: need to ensure that the person bringing the case adequately represents future and other interests. Some of those affected may not be heard by the courts. This is a particular concern in the ‘private AG’ cases. The courts will need to take a role here to ensure that these interests are represented throughout proceedings —however, the courts aren’t well equipped to do this.
• Lord Diplock in IRC was wrong to say that there should be no depth at the permission to leave stage and, further, ‘busybodies’ is not the best phrase for the people we want to exclude here —especially where “the busybody has a good and important legal point.”
• Key point is that standing would become much clearer if academics and judges were clear about the principles they think it should strive towards.
ADDITIONAL ACADEMIC LITERATURE ON STANDING
Harlow:
- Legal process is essentially bipolar / adversarial —movements which subvert that relationship undermine the key values of the legal process: certainty, finality, independence. She endorses Rose Theatre and critiques Greenpeace and WDM.
- The argument that those affected might not have effective resources, radically changes the traditional role of the courts, changing it to a generic law enforcement function / ‘machinery for accountability’.
- Advantages of pressure group standing: (i) access to justice due to financial support pressure groups can provide, e.g. CPAG; (ii) efficiency due to ability to martial resources and research (e.g. Greenpeace); (iii) ability to cope with internationalisation and HR right to litigation; (iv) pluralist / participatory democracy.
- Criticises the fact that, for pressure groups, “no serious credentials in the form of ‘democratic stake’ are required of them.”
- Disadvantages of pressure group standing: courts are becoming a surrogate for the accountability role of parliament —we could end up with the legal process becoming a ‘free for all’ (as in America) as a political tactic, as in Pergau Dam.
- She thinks that groups should have to “prove their stake” and that “the courtroom door should only be open to groups when they are genuinely offering public advocacy services.”
Argues Cane is right in saying through the idea of “democratic stake” that representativeness ought not to be assumed. But his test is not practical since “courts have no machinery for ascertaining ‘democratic stake’”. So criticizes Cane’s test as unworkable.
ADDITIONAL ACADEMIC LITERATURE ON STANDING
Williams on Harlow’s argument
- Harlow argues that we need to recognise that legal and political systems each have distinctive characteristics, and we should respect that and not let them converge like this.
- Note that Harlow’s criticisms are directed at pressure groups, but we’re now far beyond there on spectrum, we’re now at the loosest end of spectrum.
ADDITIONAL ACADEMIC LITERATURE ON STANDING
Craig: favouring a virtual citizen’s action
• Arguments for:
1. Lord Diplock in IRC on the ‘lacuna’ - vindicate RoL and stop unlawful action
2. Some illegalities affect the public at large but not any one individual
3. Woolf LJ in CPAG made the point that interest groups might raise points individual claimants would not, even if the latter is affected
• Practical objections
1. Vexatious litigants and busybodies BUT this “haunts the legal literature, not the courtroom”
2. Applicant without “personal interest will not be the most effective advocate on the issue” BUT there is “no reason to suggest any such correlation exists”
3. Clog up courts, costing money and government time BUT “it is not clear why an action that affects the public at large… is a less deserving distraction from the primary task of governing”
• Conceptual objections
1. Traditional judicial role precludes a citizen action: An attenuated connection between interest asserted and judicial action requested increases the “possibility of broadly framed challenges” — court focus “shifts from the remedying of private wrongs to the making of abstract determinations of legal principle” BUT “allowing a broad range of persons to challenge administrative action does not mean that the principle thereby propounded will be vague or untimely” Furthermore, “the subject matter in a public law case will often involve broad issues of social and political choice. The more ‘abstract’ or ‘general’ nature of the issues presented for judicial determination is not a corollary of who has standing, but of the subject-matter itself”
HUMAN RIGHTS ACT
HRA s.7:
test is whether C is a “a victim of the unlawful act”