Discretion 2 Flashcards
COLLECTION
Should Proportionality supplant Wednesbury? Intro
No, contrary to the stark choice presented by Lord Neuberger in Keyu, the 2 grounds of review can, and should, coexist.
- the content of substantive review is not exhaustive
- certain rights and interests are incommensurable. Proportionality is ill-equipped to deal with such cases.
- the criticisms addressed to Wednesbury are misplaced . They attack the test as it existed in its embryonic stage.
COLLECTION
The 2 grounds should co-exist
2 main inadequacies with proportionality for it to fully ‘supplant’ Wednesbury.
- P is ill-suited to cases which do not involve human rights. This criticism was foreseen in Rotherham MBC, in which it was suggested that P can only be used where there is ‘deviation from a legal standard’. Moreover, it could only deal with the ‘right kind of cases’. Hickman and Taggart elaborate on this, arguing that proportionality cases require a ‘rights motor’. Similarly, uncertainty about P’s ability to deal with all cases can be found in judgments of Lady Hale and Kerr in Keyu. Kerr noted that a ‘more loosely structure’ P could be used. An example case is Corner House.
In addition, Quila illustrates the kinds of cases which P may struggle with. In that case, the HS changed a policy to disallow entry clearance to spouses under 21. The legitimate aim would be to prevent forced marriag. However, the court held that the interests of those betwee 18-21 (Art 8(1) ECHR) were interfered with. Lord Brown dissenting questions whether the suffering sustained within a forced marriage could be compared with the temporary interference with the desire to marry for those between 18-21 He ultimately held that such a question is for an ‘elected politician, not judges’.
On the other hand, the case of Fedesa demonstrates that proportionality can be used to a less intensive form than Wednesbury. This raises a question: why replace W with a parallel doctrine of proportionality or ‘proportionality lite’ as Elliott puts it? Ultimately the view that we must choose between proportionality and W ‘may be very misplaced’ (Lord Kerr Keyu).
COLLECTION
Arguments for P supplanting W
Recent SC cases Kennedy, Pham and Youseff reinforce Sedley LJ’s claim in Quila that proportionality now has a ‘life of its own’ and may ‘subsume’ W. There are two arguments.
First, Lord Mance in Kennedy argued that implementation of P would provide ‘structure’ to JR proceedings. This is a view passionately advanced by Paul Craig. Lord Carnwath similarly took the view in Yousseff that all authorities should be reviewed but the more structured guidance was required for the lower courts. This corresponds with criticism of W.
Secondly, Jowell and Lester argued that W is ‘tautologist’ because no reasonable public authority would have taken it. However, ‘no reasonable’ is not exactly ‘any reasonable’. Further, the opacity of the test can bee seen in Wheeler v Leicester CC. The Council prevented a rugby team from using its facilities because the rugby team failed to sanction its players who were on tour in apartheid SA. Lord BW dissenting in the CA identified loosely freedom of expression as the norm. The HL, agreeing with LBW held that the council was ‘unlawful in its decision. It is not clear from the judgments why the HL decided as they did. Jowell and Lester add that the ‘incantation of unreasonableness’ is not in itself adequate justification. ‘Intellectual honesty’ requires more thorough and clear explanation.
Both these arguments are fighting with a W that does not exist. W is not a monolithic test but varies from large discretion in cases of policy i.e. Hammersmith v Fulham to ‘anxious scrutiny’ in Budacay per Lord bridge, Brind and Smith. This flexibility was summed up in Pham, whereby the ‘context will determine the appropriate level of review’.
Ultimately what matters is the culture of review - a ‘culture of justification’ (Taggart) will correspond with greater review, regardless of the tool of review. Further, the claim that using one over the other which carry a connotation of restraint (W) or interference (P) could be easily remedies by a clear statement form a higher court that there should be no default intensity by virtue of its connotation, thus rewriting its intensity.
COLLECTION
Should P supplant W?
positing W and P against one another establishes a false dichotomy. Doctrines should only be dismantled of they can be replaced by more useful instruments. Yet, P suffers from inherent inadequacies. Remedying when another tool exists may not be worth it. Moreover, criticisms of W are misplaced, as they attack the ground as it was in its nascent form. Ultimately the onus is on P to make its case, and it has failed to make a successful one.
What is W review?
Lord Greene MR in Associated Provincial Picture Houses Ltd v Wednesbury Corporation [1948] 1 KB 223:
“It is true that the discretion must be exercised reasonably. Now what does that mean? Lawyers familiar with the phraseology commonly used in relation to the exercise of statutory discretions often use the word ‘unreasonable’ in a rather comprehensive sense. It has frequently been used and is frequently used as a general description of the things that must not be done. For instance, a person entrusted with a discretion must, so to speak, direct himself properly in law. He must call his own attention to the matters which he is bound to consider. He must exclude from his consideration matters which are irrelevant to what he has to consider. If he does not obey those rules, he may truly be said, and often is said, to be acting ‘unreasonably’. Similarly, there may be something so absurd that no sensible person could ever dream that it lay within the powers of the authority. Warrington LJ in Short v Poole Corporation [1926] Ch 66 at 90-1 gave the example of the red-haired teacher, dismissed because she had red hair. That is unreasonable in one sense. In another sense, it is taking into consideration extraneous matters. It is so unreasonable that it might almost be described as being done in bad faith; and in fact all these things run into one another”
NB unreasonableness must be ‘overwhelming’, ‘absurd’ and beyond the dreams of ‘sensible people’ and ‘reasonable authorities’.
See also Lord Diplock in his famous restatement of the principle in GCHQ [1985] AC 374
“‘Irrationality’ by now can stand upon its own feet as an accepted ground on which a decision may be attacked by judicial review’.
“by ‘irrationality’ I mean what can now be succinctly referred to as ‘Wednesbury unreasonableness’… It applies to a decision which is so outrageous in its defiance of logic or accepted moral standards that no sensible person who had applied his mind to the question to be decided could have arrived at it”
Justified because reserved the review/appeal distinction:
“Whether a decision falls within this category is a question that judges by their training and experience should be well equipped to answer, or else there would be something badly wrong with our judicial system”.
Irvine [1996] PL 59 (theoretical criticims)
See also Irvine [1996] PL 59:
- The constitutional imperative; that once Parliament has entrusted a body with the ability to make a decision the courts should not lightly interfere with this.
- The lack of judicial expertise when compared with that of the decision-maker and
- The democratic mandate, that the courts should not usurp political, democratic controls on the executive.
NB: Jowell justifies judicial deference on these grounds too, using the concepts of “constitutional competence” (separation of powers, which delimits the proper role of various institutions in a democracy) and “institutional competence” (the institutional limitations on what the courts are able to do, as opposed to decision-makers).
The current status of Wednesbury unreasonableness
Two important points about the original conception of Wednesbury;
- It looks, as John Laws puts it (in Forsyth and Hare (eds) The Golden Metwand and the Crooked Cord at 186-7), “monolithic”, i.e. it represented a fixed standard
- That standard looks extremely high.
Different standard of W in field of public administration
Nottinghamshire County Council v Secretary of State for the Environment [1986] AC 240 Lord Scarman:
To sum it up, the levels of public expenditure and the incidence and distribution of taxation are matters for Parliament
, as in this case, effect cannot be given to the Secretary of State’s determination without the consent of the House of Commons and the House of Commons has consented, it is not open to the courts to intervene unless the Minister and the House must have misconstrued the statute or the Minister has – to put it bluntly – deceived the House…
See also R v Ministry of Defence, ex p Smith [1996] QB 517 at 556, Sir Thomas Bingham:
“The greater the policy content of a decision, and the more remote the subject matter of a decision from ordinary judicial experience, the more hesitant the court must necessarily be in holding a decision to be irrational. That is good law and, like most good law, common sense… the test itself is sufficiently flexible to cover all situations.”
The more substantial the interference with human rights, the more the court will require by way of justification before it is satisfied that the decision is reasonable”
W in Bugdaycay Lord Bridge absence of the HRA
“surely does not mean that… we are not perfectly entitled to start from the premise that any restriction of the right to freedom of expression requires to be justified and that nothing less than an important competing public interest will be sufficient to justify it… we are entitled to exercise a secondary judgment by asking whether a reasonable Secretary of State, on the material before him, could reasonably make that primary judgment” (at 531, emphasis added).
W outside of human rights contexts
Coughlan on decisions made through “flawed logic”.
See also Lord Mance in Kennedy v Charity Commissioners (Lords Neuberger and Clarke agreeing) on W
[51]….The common law no longer insists on the uniform application of the rigid test of irrationality once thought applicable under the so- calledWednesburyprinciple: seeAssociated Provincial Picture Houses Ltd v Wednesbury Corpn [1948] 1 KB 223. The nature of judicial review in every case depends on the context.
Does this change reflect an adaption of W?
Craig 21-011:
“the idea that heightened scrutiny in cases concerning rights can be seen simply as a variant of the original Wednesbury test is problematic in both linguistic and conceptual terms.”
“In conceptual terms, it is equally difficult to regard judicial review in rights cases merely as a variant of traditional Wednesbury, since the premises that underlie review in the two contexts differ. The premise that underpins the classic Wednesbury approach, as overlaid by Lord Diplock, is that the courts should be aware of their limited role.
Diplock prophecy
Lord Diplock in GCHQ: no reason why
“further development on a case by case basis may not in course of time add further grounds. I have in mind particularly the adoption in the future of the principle of ‘proportionality’ which is recognised in the administrative law of several of our fellow members of the EEC [as it then was]”
What is proportionality?
What is proportionality?
Lord Sumption in Bank Mellat v Her Majesty’s Treasury (No 2) [2013] UKSC 38 identified four issues in particular for consideration under proportionality review:
- Whether the legislative objective is sufficiently important to justify limiting a fundamental right
- Whether the legislative objective is rationally connected to the means used to achieve it (suitability)
- Whether the means used are no more than is necessary to accomplish that objective (necessity)
- Whether a fair balance has been struck between the rights of the individual and the interests of the community (‘proportionality stricto sensu’ or a test of fair balance)
- Whether the measure has a legitimate aim in the first place
1 is separate from but connected to the fair balance issue (cf Lord Kerr, dissenting in Carlile [2014] 3 WLR 1404), 5 is essentially a basic vires question. This leaves the three issues of suitability, necessity and fair balance
Is P intensity fixed?
[54] As Lord Bingham explained [in Eastside Cheese], at para 47, proportionality review may itself be limited in context to examining whether the exercise of a power involved some manifest error or clear excess of the bounds of discretion
So when can and do the courts use proportionality review?
- EU law, e.g. if the national administrative court has to check whether the UK’s derogation from the free movement of goods rules is proportionate, e.g. the ITF case. See also the International Stock Exchange case, ex p Else [1992] BCC 11. NB failure by the decision-maker to have regard to this duty to act proportionately may overlap with one of the other grounds of review and constitute a failure to take into account a relevant consideration as in Lindsay v Commissioners of Customs and Excise [2002] EWCA Civ 267. Future of this category of course now depends on our future relationship with EU law.
- Human rights cases
a. HRA cases (see subsequent lectures)
b. Common Law rights cases, e.g. Brind and Bugdaycay. NB now the increasing use of common law rights, e.g. R (Quila) v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2011] UKSC 45
Domestic, non-HRA law:
- Statutory requirement to use proportionality, e.g. Bank Mellat, above.
- Substantive legitimate expectation cases. ex p Coughlan, Lord Woolf MR: “once the legitimacy of the expectation is established, the court will have the task of weighing the requirements of fairness against any overriding interest relied upon for the change of policy” “It required the health authority, as a matter of fairness, not to resile from their promise unless there was an overriding justification for doing so. Another way of expressing the same thing is to talk of the unwarranted frustration of a legitimate expectation and thus an abuse of power or a failure of substantive fairness. Again, the labels are not important…They identify a different task for the court from that where what is in issue is a conventional application of policy or exercise of discretion. Here the decision can only be justified if there is an overriding public interest. Whether there is an overriding public interest is a question for the court.” NB the distinction from Wednesbury: “For our part, in relation to this category of legitimate expectation, we do not consider it necessary to explain the modern doctrine in Wednesbury terms, helpful though this is in terms of received jurisprudence” Compare Nadarajah, Abdi v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2005] EWCA Civ 1363 see Laws LJ at [69] referring to proportionality, with Lord Mance, dissenting in R(Bancoult) v Secretary of State for Foreign and Commonwealth Affairs (No 2), [2008] UKHL 61, [2009] 1 AC 453, at [182]: ‘overtones of another area of public law’. But see also the PC in Paponette v AG of Trinidad and Tobago [2010] UKPC 32.
- Penalty cases, e.g. ex p Hook [1976] 1 WLR 1052. Lord Denning MR: “there are old cases which show that the court can interfere by certiorari if a punishment is altogether excessive and out of proportion to the occasion.” On this see also R v Manchester Metropolitan University ex p Nolan (unrep 14th July 1993) in which Sedley J held that he would “assume for this purpose that proportionality is potentially available today as a discrete head of challenge in appropriate cases.”
- Miscellaneous cases
a. in which the unreasonableness seems to stem from disproportionality, e.g. Bryan v Secretary of State for the Environment CA unrep 5/3/93, cited by de Búrca (Ch 4 of Andenas ed English Public Law and the Common Law of Europe (1998)) in which Legatt LJ held that he would “proceed upon the footing that the court will quash in a proper case as Wednesbury unreasonable, if not directly under the principle of proportionality, the exercise of a discretionary power in which the means used is out of proportion to the object sought to be achieved”. (See also R v General Medical Council ex p Colman [1990] 1 All ER 489; R v Secretary of State for Transport ex p Pegasus Holdings [1988] 1 WLR 990; R v Brent BC ex p Assegai Times 18th June 1987, R v Secretary of State for Health ex p US Tobacco [1992] QB 353).
b. In which proportionality seems to be used outright, e.g. ex p Phoenix Aviation [1995] 3 All ER 37: Council’s resolution to ban Phoenix air from transporting live animals due to the threat of animal rights protests “was wholly disproportionate to the security risk presented at that time”
Authorities against P
R v Secretary of State for the Home Department ex p Brind [1991] 1 AC 696 per Lord Lowry:
“there is no authority for saying that proportionality in the sense in which the appellants have used it is part of the English common law and a great deal of authority the other way. This, so far as I am concerned, is not a cause of regret for several reasons”
Lord Slynn in R (Alconbury) v Secretary of State for the Environment, Transport and the Regions [2001] UKHL 23:
“the time has come to recognise that this principle is part of English administrative law, not only when judges are dealing with Community acts, but also when they are dealing with acts subject to domestic law. Trying to keep the Wednesbury principle and proportionality in separate compartments seems to me to be unnecessary and confusing”
Evidence that the tests are not too different
John Laws in R(Mahmood) v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2001] 1 WLR 840 at [19] the higher intensity review to be performed in human rights cases “and the basic Wednesbury rule are by no means hermetically sealed one from the other. There is, rather, what may be called a sliding scale of review.” Wade and Forsyth agree that “it must be emphasised that they are flexible doctrines, depending often upon value judgments and factual evidence, having no sharp edges. They cannot, in Lord Slynn’s words, be kept in separate compartments” (p. 368).
ex p ITF Lord Slynn (at p 439) “in some ways they are though the distinction between the two tests in practice is in any event much less than is sometimes suggested.”
Wade and Forsyth
“Goodbye to Wednesbury?” (p 371): “The Wednesbury doctrine is now in terminal decline, but the coup de grace has not yet fallen, despite calls for it from very high authorities”.
Kennedy v Information Commissioner Lord Mance (Lords Neuberger and Clarke agreeing) suggested a different approach:
[54] The advantage of the terminology of proportionality is that it introduces an element of structure into the exercise, by directing attention to factors such as suitability or appropriateness, necessity and the balance or imbalance of benefits and disadvantages. There seems no reason why such factors should not be relevant in judicial review even outside the scope of Convention and EU law.
What did Lord Neuberger and Hughes hold in Keyu?
It would not be appropriate for a five-justice panel of this court to accept, or indeed to reject, this argument, which potentially has implications which are profound in constitutional terms and very wide in applicable scope….
[133] The move from rationality to proportionality, as urged by the appellants, would appear to have potentially profound and far reaching consequences, because it would involve the court considering the merits of the decision at issue:
- nb would it??