Metatheorems Flashcards

1
Q

40.1

A

If A is logically valid, then ~A is not satisfiable.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
2
Q

40.2

A

If a sequence s satisfies A and also A ⊃ B, then it also satisfies B.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
3
Q

40.3

A

If A and A ⊃ B are both true for an interpretation I, then B is also true for I.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
4
Q

40.4

A

If A and A ⊃ B are both logically valid, then so is B.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
5
Q

40.5

A

A is false for a given interpretation iff ~A is true; and A is true for I iff ~A is false for I.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
6
Q

40.6

A

A is true for I iff ∧vA is true for I for any arbitrary variable v.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
7
Q

40.7

A

A is true for I iff any arbitrary closure of A is true for I.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
8
Q

40.8

A

A is logically valid iff Ac is.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
9
Q

40.9

A

∨vA is satisfiable for an interpretation iff A is satisfiable for the same interpretation.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
10
Q

40.13

A

If vk does not occur free in A, then A ⊃ ∧vkA is logically valid.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
11
Q

40.14

A

Let t and u be terms. Let t′ be the result of replacing each occurrence of vk in t by u. Let s be a sequence, and let us = d. In other words, let the member of D assigned by I to u for the sequence s be d. Let s′ be the sequence that results from substituting d for the kth term of s. Then, t′s = t*s′. In other words, the member of D assigned by I to t′ is the same as the member of D assigned by I to t for sequence s′.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
12
Q

40.15

A

Let A be a wff, vk a variable, t a term that is free for vk in A. Let s be a sequence, and let s′ be the sequence that results from replacing the kth term of s by t*s. Then, s satisfies At/vk iff s′ satisfies A.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
13
Q

40.16

A

∧vkA ⊃ At/vk is logically valid if t is free for vk in A.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
14
Q

40.17

A

If A is a closed wff, then exactly on of A and ~A is true, and exactly one false.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
15
Q

43.5

A

Every theorem of QS is logically valid.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
16
Q

43.7

A

If A is a syntactic consequence of Γ in QS, then A is a semantic consequence of Γ in Q.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
17
Q

45.4

A

If A is a theorem of K, then ∧vA is a theorem of K.

18
Q

45.5

A

A is a theorem of k iff Ac is a theorem of K.

19
Q

45.6

A

If A is a closed wff of K that is not a theorem of K, then K + {~A} is a consistent first order theory.

20
Q

45.8

A

If a first order theory has a model, then it is consistent.

21
Q

45.11

A

If K is a consistent first order theory, then the system that results from adding a denumerable set of new individual constants to K, with an effective enumeration of those
constants, is a consistent first order theory that is an extension of K.

22
Q

45.13

A

If K is a consistent first order theory, then there is a first order theory K′ that is a consistent, closed, and negation-complete extension of K.

23
Q

45.14

A

Any consistent, closed, negation-complete first order theory has a denumerable model. (Alternative in 45.16): Any consistent set of closed wff of a first order theory has a denumerable model.

24
Q

45.16

A

Any consistent set of closed wff of a first order theory has a denumerable model.

25
Q

45.15 (The Key Theorem)

A

Any consistent first order theory has a denumerable model.

26
Q

45.17 (Godel’s Theorem)

A

Any consistent set of wffs of a first order theory is simultaneously satisfiable in a denumerable domain.

Lemma 1: If Γ is a consistent set of a first order theory K, and K′ is a first order theory that results from merely adding denumerably many new individual constants to K, then Γ is a consistent set of K′.

Lemma 2: Let A be a wff in which some variable v has one or more free occurrences. Let c be a constant that does not occur in A or in any proper axiom of K. Then if Ac/v is a theorem of K, A is a theorem of K.

27
Q

45.18 (Lowenheim-Skolem Theorem)

A

If a first order theory has a model, then it has a denumerable model.

28
Q

45.19

A

If there is an interpretation I for which every proper axiom of a first order theory K is true, then K has a model.

29
Q

45.20 (The compactness theorem for K)

A

If every finite subset of the set of proper axioms of a first order theory K has a model, then K has a model.

30
Q

45.21

A

If A is a syntactic consequence of Γ in K, and v does not occur free in Γ, then ∧vA is a syntactic consequence of Γ in K. (An extension of 45.4)

31
Q

45.22

A

If v has no free occurrence in B, then ∧v(A ⊃ B) ⊃ (∨vA ⊃ B) is a theorem of K.

32
Q

45.23

A

If a variable u does not occur in A, then ∨vA ⊃ ∨uAu/v.

33
Q

45.25

A

If t is a closed term of K, then At/v ⊃ ∨vA is a theorem of K.

34
Q

46.1 (The Semantic Completeness Theorem for QS)

A

Every logically valid formula of Q is a theorem of QS.

35
Q

46.2 (The Strong Completeness Theorem for QS)

A

If A is a semantic consequence of Γ in Q, then A is a syntactic consequence of Γ in QS.

36
Q

46.4

A

QS is negation-complete.

37
Q

47.1

A

QS= is consistent.

38
Q

47.2

A

If K is a consistent first order theory with identity, then K has a countable normal model.

39
Q

47.3

A

Any formula of Q that is true for every normal interpretation of Q is a theorem of QS=.

40
Q

48.2

A

If M and M′ are isomorphic models of a first order theory of K, then a formula A of K is true for M iff it is true for M′.

41
Q

48.3

A

If all normal models of a first order theory with identity are isomorphic, then the theory is negation complete. In other words, if a first order theory with identity is 2-categorical (All its normal models are isomorphic, then it is negation-complete).