Human Rights and Land Flashcards
What does Gray, ‘Land Law and Human Rights’ say about the principle that no one should be arbitrarily deprived of their property found in A1P1?
The human right to protection from arbitrary dispossession by the state is born of a deep impulse which views lawless seizure of property as a particularly violating kind of molestation—a form of proprietary rape.
For Blackstone, writing in 1765, it was inconceivable that ‘sacred and inviolable rights to private property’ should be postponed to ‘public necessity’ without ‘a full indemnification and equivalent for the injury thereby sustained’.
What does Malik v Fassenfelt [2013] say about the sanctity of the home?
The sanctity of the home that forms the basis of Art 8 also reflects the fundamental sentiment that the home is a personal inviolable space reflected in the time-honoured phrase that ‘an Englishman’s home is his castle’.
What does Bright say about the far reaching impact of the HRA on our concepts of ownership? (Landmark Cases: Pinnock)
The right to recover possession of land that is occupied as a home by someone with no lawful right to occupy can no longer be seen as automatic, no longer a foregone conclusion that flows from a simple application of a traditional understanding of the hierarchy of rights in land [. . .] Article 8 requires a new way of thinking about the right to recover possession.
When Article 8 is engaged, and raised as defence, the owner will not be entitled to an order for possession merely by showing that the occupier has no lawful right to occupy; it will be necessary to show that the recovery of possession is justified by the pursuit of a legitimate aim [. . .]
The proportionality question does require a shift towards a contextualised, non-hierarchical way of thinking, in which factors extraneous to property doctrine come into play [. . .] This is a different way of thinking about ownership.
What two hurdles does Goymour explain that a litigant must clear?
First a State’s liability must be engaged because the law is incompatible with the ECHR, and secondly the HRA 1998 must provide a route by which that breach can be relied upon in the domestic courts.
What is the Court’s duty under the HRA 1998?
It must take into account any judgment of Strasbourg jurisprudence in the interpretation of rights enshrined in the ECHR.
Can the SC diverge from Strasbourg jurisprudence?
In R v Hardcastle it was suggested that the Supreme Court should enjoy a degree of latitude where they believe that the Strasbourg Court does not appreciate the domestic context. A dissatisfied victim may then appeal to the Strasbourg Court resulting in a dialogue, through the judgments of the two courts, to hopefully resolve any misunderstanding. Nevertheless, no such dialogue is appropriate where there is a clear and consistent line of authority from the Strasbourg Court.
Lord Bingham in R (Ullah) v Special Adjudicator
‘[t]he duty of national courts is to keep pace with the Strasbourg jurisprudence as it evolves over time: no more, but certainly no less.’
Thus, Strasbourg Court decisions have tended to operate as a ceiling on the development of our domestic human rights
What are the facts of James v UK (1986)?
The Duke of Westminster, whose estate comprised a significant number of houses in London let on long leases, unsuccessfully questioned the compatibility with Art 1 of the First Protocol of the Leasehold Reform Act 1967. The Act entitled the tenants of the houses to require him to transfer the freehold reversion to them for sums (as defined by the legislation) that were less than their market value.
What was held in James v UK re the margin of appreciation?
Because of their direct knowledge of their society and its needs, the national authorities are in principle better placed than the international judge to appreciate what is “in the public interest.”
Under the system of protection established by the Convention, it is thus for the national authorities to make the initial assessment both of the existence of the problem of public concern warranting measures of deprivation of property and of the remedial action to be taken [. . .] Here as in other fields to which the safeguards of the Convention extend, the national authorities accordingly enjoy a certain margin of appreciation.
Furthermore, the notion of “public interest” is necessarily extensive, in particular, as the Commission noted, the decision to enact laws expropriating property will commonly involve consideration of political, economic and social issues on which opinions within a democratic society may reasonably differ widely. The Court finding it natural that the margin of appreciation available to the legislature in implementing social and economic policies should be a wide one, will respect the legislature’s judgment as to what is “in the public interest” unless that judgment be manifestly without reasonable foundation [. . .]
When will a State’s actions taken in the public interest under A1P1 be respected?
- standard
- Art 2 HRA?
- how this margin varies
will be respected unless they are ‘manifestly without reasonable foundation’, in the sense that no reasonable government would have come to a similar decision in the circumstances.
It should be noted that in pursuance of their obligations under s 2 of the HRA 1998, the domestic courts, save in exceptional circumstances, will accept the compatibility of a law which the Strasbourg Court has held to be within the United Kingdom’s margin of appreciation
But this margin will depend on the Article in question.
What were the facts in Connors v UK (2005)?
The Connors were gypsies. The family occupied the same local authority site under a licence for over thirteen years, but, after their daughter married and their sons grew up, it was alleged that their pitch was a ‘magnet for trouble’. As a result, the local authority terminated their licence to occupy and summarily evicted them from the site, but without citing any reasons. The local authority chose not to rely upon the (p. 95) Connors’ alleged ‘antisocial’ behaviour. The Connor family successfully claimed that their summary eviction breached their rights to respect for their home and way of life as gypsies under Art 8.
What was said in Connor about the margin of appreciation?
- why is it left to national authorities?
- how does this margin vary?
- authority?
- what has the Court stated re housing?
- what issues are of great importance with Art 8?
a margin of appreciation must, inevitably, be left to the national authorities, who by reason of their direct and continuous contact with the vital forces of their countries are in principle better placed than an international court to evaluate local needs and conditions.
This margin will vary according to the nature of the Convention right in issue, its importance for the individual and the nature of the activities restricted, as well as the nature of the aim pursued by the restrictions.
The margin will tend to be narrower where the right at stake is crucial to the individual’s effective enjoyment of intimate or key rights. [. . .]
On the other hand, in spheres involving the application of social or economic policies, there is authority that the margin of appreciation is wide, as in the planning context where the Court has found that: “[i]n so far as the exercise of discretion involving a multitude of local factors is inherent in the choice and implementation of planning policies, the national authorities in principle enjoy a wide margin of appreciation”. Buckley v United Kingdom (1997) 23 E.H.R.R. 101 at [75].
The Court has also stated that in spheres such as housing, which play a central role in the welfare and economic policies of modern societies, it will respect the legislature’s judgment as to what is in the general interest unless that judgment is manifestly without reasonable foundation.
It may be noted however that this was in the context of Art.1 of Protocol No.1, not Art.8 which concerns rights of central importance to the individual’s identity, self-determination, physical and moral integrity, maintenance of relationships with others and a settled and secure place in the community.
What did Kay v UK (2012) hold re procedural safeguards?
it is clear from the case law of the Court that the requirement under art.8(2) that the interference be “necessary in a democratic society” raises a question of procedure as well as one of substance. (Connors v UK, McCann v UK).
The procedural safeguards available to the individual will be especially material in determining whether the respondent State has, when fixing the regulatory framework, remained within its margin of appreciation. In particular, the Court must examine whether the decision-making process leading to measures of interference was fair and such as to afford due respect to the interests safeguarded to the individual by Article 8 (Buckley v UK, Chapman v UK, and Connors v UK).
What does Nield (‘Clash of the Titan’) argue?
It would be tempting to conclude that whilst on matters of the substantive content of the law implementing a particular social or economic policy, where a party is granted a right to possession against another, the State’s margin of appreciation remains wide; but as a matter of the procedural operation of that policy, where the consequences dictate repossession of an individual’s home, the margin is narrow. But this distinction is too simplistic. The two issues are intimately entwined because the substantive law will define the circumstances when the occupier may be heard before the court [. . .] As Loveland has succinctly put the issue [referring to McCann v UK]; ‘it is not what the council had done but what the court could not do’.
What are the four limbs of proportionality?
- legitimate objective
- suitability
- minimal impairment
- overall balance
What are the two levels of intensity operating in proportionality?
- fair balance struck between individual convention rights and the general interest of the public or society
- proportionality of the impact of the law as applied to an individual victim in the particular circumstances (operates at a micro-level)
What does Neild note about deference?
- Qazi
- Kay
is this approach surprising?
Thus, should deference be automatic?
In assessing the proper extent of judicial deference, context is everything. Qazi demonstrates an extreme degree of deference in which proprietary rights to possession are not to be questioned at all—they were in fact nonjusticiable!
In Kay the House of Lords has shown, in both the views of the majority and minority, that in relation to the regulation of housing they will show exceptional deference to the policy choices of Parliament.
This is not surprising given both the degree of Parliamentary scrutiny of housing policy and the public funding underpinning that policy. Similar substantial deference is to be expected in relation to proprietary rules governing possession where certainty and due balancing of the rights of third parties is necessary.
However, it should not mean that the ECHR compatibility of proprietary rules should be non-justiciable or even that substantial deference should be automatic. Judicial deference should be assessed on a case-by-case (or rule-by-rule) basis.
Direct Effect of HRA
s 7 of the HRA 1998 confers upon a victim of an infringement of his or her human rights by a public authority a direct cause of action so that he or she may bring proceedings against, or defend proceedings brought by, that authority.
A ‘victim’ is a person who is directly affected by the act or omission of the public authority. Where the court finds that a public authority has failed to act as required by s 6, the court may grant such remedy as it deems to be ‘just and appropriate’, including the award of damages
What counts as a public authority?
- Core public authority: A core public authority is required to comply with the ECHR in the performance of all of its functions because it is a public authority ‘through and through’
- hybrid public authorities: only required to comply with the ECHR when exercising those functions that are of a public nature.
London Quadrant Housing Trust v Weaver’s guidance on when an act of terminating the tenancy is a private act?
Elias LJ: it is in my view important to focus on the context in which the act occurs; the act cannot be considered in isolation simply asking whether it involves the exercise of a private law power or not.
Number of features which point to public:
- Trust’s function in allocating and managing housing; reliance on public finance
- Does not directly take the place of local government but it operates in very close harmony with it
- provision of subsidised housing, as opposed to the provision of housing itself, is a function which can properly be described as governmental
Further considerations: (a) charitable objectives; (b) regulation it is subject to designed to render activities more transparent
Therefore, even though termination seems contractual, it is part of a public function so subject to HRA considerations.
What did Rix LJ (dissenting in Weaver) argue?
He was strongly of the view that in terminating a tenancy a social landlord was exercising a private right conferred by a private tenancy agreement and didn’t think London Quadrant was a hybrid public authority
What is the standard of review when public authority’s decision is subject to JR?
courts look beyond conventional Wednesbury to standard of proportionality when dealing with HRs (Daly, Begum)
What is the interface between s. 7 human rights cause of action and public law action by JR?
Walker LJ in Taylor v Central Bedfordshire Council [2009] EWCA Civ 613, [38] that the distinction ‘has, very largely, become academic’.
But, judicial review empowers the courts to intervene to question a public authority’s decision but no overt duty is placed upon the public authority itself. Whereas standards of legality, whether derived from the rules of natural justice or the HRA 1998, impose duties upon public authorities that the courts, as adjudicators, decide whether or not have been met. Standards of legality, thus, look to what the public authority is lawfully able to do and standards of review can question how they do so.
What 6 different ways can horizontality operate?
- Direct statutory horizontality (s. 3)
- Public liability horizontality (s. 6)
3+4 The courts and remedial and procedural horizontality (s. 6)
5+6 The courts and indirect and direct horizontality (s. 6)
A1P1
Protection of property
Every natural or legal person is entitled to the peaceful enjoyment of his possessions. No one shall be deprived of his possessions except in the public interest and subject to the conditions provided for by law and by the general principles of international law.
The preceding provisions shall not, however, in any way impair the right of a State to enforce such laws as it deems necessary to control the use of property in accordance with the general interest or to secure the payment of taxes or other contributions or penalties.
What is the object of A1P1?
Article 1 provides a right of property and not to property. Its object is thus to protect existing property that a person holds by both positively guaranteeing that a person is entitled to the peaceful enjoyment of his or her property, and by providing supporting negative prohibitions upon a person being deprived of his or her possession or being subject to controls over his or her enjoyment of those possessions, unless such incursions can be justified in the public or general interest.
What 20 philosophical starting points does Gray highlight?
In most areas of property law there exists a tension between two philosophical starting points, which may perhaps be characterised as the perspectives of the property absolutist and the property relativist. Most lay persons tend, by natural disposition, to be property absolutists – in that they believe passionately and instinctively that ownership of an estate in land confers inviolable and exclusive rights of enjoyment and exploitation. By contrast the property relativist pictures property in terms, not of absolute rights, but rather of qualified entitlements based on social accommodation, community-directed obligation and notions of reasonable user. The dominant modern juristic perception of property is, without much doubt, that of the relativist, partly because the pressures of crowded urban coexistence have forced a fresh recognition of the heavily interdependent nature of our social and economic arrangements. There remain today few true property absolutists, although those who tend towards this view maintain that all regulatory interference with land use necessarily constitutes a compensable ‘taking’ of property. In its most unqualified form, the absolutist approach castigates uncompensated regulation as environmental fascism and insists that if the community wants environmental welfare, it must purchase it fairly rather than simply dump the unalleviated cost on isolated owners of real estate.
When is A1P1 engaged?
When there has been an interference with possession under one of the three elements of the Article identified by Strasbourg in Sporrong
Sporrong
The first rule, which is of a general nature, announces the principle of peaceful enjoyment of property; it is set out in the first sentence of the first paragraph. The second rule covers deprivation of possessions and subjects it to certain conditions; it appears in the second sentence of the same paragraph. The third rule recognizes that the States are entitled, amongst other things, to control the use of property in accordance with the general interest, by enforcing such laws as they deem necessary for the purpose; it is contained in the second paragraph.
The courts will look to see whether the last two rules are applicable before considering whether the first rule has been infringed.
James v UK on the interrelated nature of the rules
The three rules are not however “distinct” in the sense of being unconnected. The second and third rules are concerned with particular instances of interference with the right to peaceful enjoyment of property and should therefore be construed in the light of the general principle enunciated in the first rule.
The rule (in the second sentence) subjects deprivation of possessions to certain conditions concerns a particular category, indeed of the most radical kind, of interference with the right to peaceful enjoyment of property [. . .]; the second sentence supplements and qualifies the general principle enunciated in the first sentence. This being so, it is inconceivable that application of the general principle to the present case should lead to any conclusion different from that already arrived at by the court in the application of the second sentence.
Meaning of possession
‘autonomous’ definition, meaning Strasbourg interprets it.
Has done so widely: there is no doubt that our established notions of estates and interests in land fall within its meaning. The term also covers other accepted categories of property rights that fall outside the scope of this book, such as personal and intellectual property, as well as rights that may arise from contractual relations, a tortious claim etc.
But, an expectation that you might receive property (i.e. inheritance) is not possession.
Thus, unclear whether an inchoate equity (i.e. arising by estoppel) constitutes possession for A1P1.
Stretch shows there is the possibility, at least where a public authority raises a legitimate expectation of entitlement
What does deprivation of possession mean (second limb of A1P1)?
A ‘deprivation’ is generally defined by a transfer or shift in ownership: examples include the compulsory purchase of land (Howard v UK), the nationalization of a business by the government (Lithgow v UK) or the confiscation of the proceeds of crime (R v May). The transfer need not be to the government, or other public authority; it may be to another private individual, where the State has sanctioned that transfer by legislation.
Does determination of a lease count as deprivation of possession?
- example case?
Most obviously, the determination of a lease (whether by the expiry of the term, by a notice to quit, or by a right of forfeiture) does not deprive the tenant of his or her possessions, because the lease is defined by these means of termination from the outset.
For instance, in Sims v Dacorum BC, the Supreme Court held that the exercise of a contractual right to terminate a joint lease by one joint tenant did not constitute a deprivation of possession, it was a feature of the lease itself.
Does power to sell/overreaching count as deprivation?
Goymour suggests that the question may turn on whether the power is taken to be expressly conferred, and thus defines the possession, or is a consequence of statutory imposition.
What does ‘control over land’ (third limb of A1P1) means?
A government may enact laws that control the use of land, the most obvious example being planning controls.
Rent controls and limitations upon a landlord’s right to recover their property from a tenant are further examples of controls over possessions.
More unusual examples include controls over fishing, and hunting rights over land, or controls over who can actually use the land
Deprivation or control? And why is the distinction important?
The distinction is significant when it comes to considering whether or not the interference is proportionate and in particular the payment of compensation. An extensive control over a possession may amount to a de facto expropriation where the victim is deprived of all meaningful use of their property (Sporrong).
For instance in R (on the application of Mott) v Environment Agency, controls over a lease granting a right to fish salmon in the Severn estuary which reduced the catch by 95 per cent was held to be closer to a deprivation than a control and in any event called for the payment of compensation.
What are the facts of JA Pye?
Pye owned land that it intended to develop. In the meantime, it licensed the land to a neighbouring farmer, Mr Graham. When the licence expired, Mr Graham continued in adverse possession of the land for a period in excess of the limitation period of twelve years. When Pye eventually tried to evict Mr Graham, the House of Lords dismissed its claim and held that Mr Graham was entitled to be registered as the owner. Pye unsuccessfully claimed that it had been deprived of its ownership in breach of Art 1 of the First Protocol.
What was held in JA Pye?
The applicant companies did not lose their land because of a legislative provision which permitted the State to transfer ownership in particular circumstances (as in the cases of AGOSI, Air Canada, Gasus), or because of a social policy of transfer of ownership (as in the case of James), but rather as the result of the operation of the generally applicable rules on limitation periods for actions for recovery of land.
The statutory provisions which resulted in the applicant companies’ loss of beneficial ownership were thus not intended to deprive paper owners of their ownership, but rather to regulate questions of title in a system in which, historically, 12 years’ adverse possession was sufficient to extinguish the former owner’s right to re-enter or to recover possession, and the new title depended on the principle that unchallenged lengthy possession gave a title. The provisions of the 1925 and 1980 Acts which were applied to the applicant companies were part of the general land law, and were concerned to regulate, amongst other things, limitation periods in the context of the use and ownership of land as between individuals. The applicant companies were therefore affected, not by a “deprivation of possessions” within the meaning of the second sentence of the first paragraph of Article 1, but rather by a “control of use” of land within the meaning of the second paragraph of the provision.
What does ‘peaceful enjoyment’ (first limb A1-1) mean?
example case falling within this category?
An interference that does not fall within the second or third limb may nevertheless be an interference with the peaceful enjoyment of possession under the residual category provided by the first limb.
Sporrong and Lonnroth v Sweden provides an example. The complainants owed land in Stockholm that was earmarked for development and the authorities issued expropriation notices. Although the notices were never implemented, the complainants’ ability to deal with their land was blighted. The Court found that there was no deprivation or control under the second and third limbs, but did find that there was an infringement of the first rule.
When is an interference justified?
- subject to the law
The interference must be in accordance with domestic law.
Furthermore, that domestic law must satisfy the fundamental requirements of the rule of law. It must not operate arbitrarily, it must be certain and accessible, and it must provide adequate procedural safeguards.
When is an interference justified?
- The public and general interest
It is not thought that there is a distinction between the public and general interest. These expressions define the legitimate interest in respect of which a deprivation or control may be justified. States enjoy a wide margin of appreciation in both identifying what is in the public interest and in formulating the appropriate measures to address that interest. The width of a State’s margin of appreciation is evident from James v UK
Hutten-Czapska v Poland (2007) on public and general interest
The notion of “public” or “general” interest is necessarily extensive. In particular, spheres such as housing of the population, which modern societies consider a prime social need and which plays a central role in the welfare and economic policies of contracting states, may often call for some form of regulation by the state. In that sphere decisions as to whether, and if so when, it may fully be left to the play of free market forces or whether it should be (p. 122) subject to state control, as well as the choice of measures for securing the housing needs of the community and of the timing for their implementation, necessarily involve consideration of complex social, economic and political issues.
Compensation and A1P1
Article 1 does not expressly do so, but the Strasbourg Court has made clear that where the second limb of the Article is engaged (i.e. where there is a deprivation of property), compensation is to be expected, although that compensation may be less than market value. (Holy Monasteries v Greece (1995) )
James v UK on compensation in A1P1
the protection of the right to property it affords would be largely illusory and ineffective in the absence of any equivalent principle. Clearly compensation terms are material to the assessment whether the contested legislation respects a fair balance between the various interests at stake and, notably, it does not impose a disproportionate burden on the applicants
Procedural safeguards and A1P1
Zehentner v Austria: Strasbourg Court held that in respect of Art 1 Protocol 1 the judicial sale of the victim’s property was a disproportionate interference with the victim’s property, given the relatively small debts involved, and because the process took no account of the victim’s incapacity. Furthermore, the procedural possibility of challenging the debts themselves on the grounds of the victim’s lack of capacity did not constitute a viable alternative.
Chamber’s decision in Pye was also premised on the lack of procedural safeguards afforded to the paper owner whose registered title was automatically extinguished but the grand Chamber thought the safeguards were adequate
Article 8 ECHR
- Everyone has the right to respect for his private and family life, his home and his correspondence.
- There shall be no interference by a public authority with the exercise of this right except such as is in accordance with the law and is necessary in a democratic society in the interests of national security, public safety or the economic well-being of the country, for the prevention of disorder or crime, for the protection of health or morals, or for the protection of the rights and freedoms of others.
When is Article 8(1) engaged?
‘Home’ has an autonomous meaning, being a place of residence with which the individual has ‘sufficient and continuing links’, and is not dependent upon that person having a legal right of occupation. This test was developed by the Strasbourg Court in the case of Gillow v UK, and has been consistently applied in subsequent cases by the Strasbourg Court, the House of Lords, and the Supreme Court.
Harrow LBC v Qazi [2004] on ‘home’
Lord Bingham:
Not surprisingly, the need for some protection of the home was recognised in the Convention, since few things are more central to the enjoyment of human life than having somewhere to live. On a straightforward reading of the Convention, its use of the expression “home” appears to invite a down-to-earth and pragmatic consideration whether [. . .] the place in question is that where a person “lives and to which he returns and which forms the centre of his existence”, since “home” is not a legal term of art and article 8 is not directed to the protection of property interests or contractual rights.
What do Nield and Hopkins suggest about when Article 8 should be considered?
Accordingly the Art 8 rights of family members with no property interest, for example, children should be considered
Is the legality of their possession relevant?
Even though an occupier’s legal right to remain in possession may have ceased, or indeed never arisen, their residence may still qualify as their home for the purposes of Art 8(1).
The legality of their occupation is relevant only to the justification balance under Art 8(2). Looking beyond property rights raises the possibility that Art 8 may offer a new measure of human rights based protection of the home