Hardwig: Dying at the Right Time: Reflections on (Un) Assisted Suicide Flashcards
The timing of death
it doesn’t always come at the right time. death can come too soon but it can also come too late
the social context of dying
- the individualistic fantasy is a flawed way of thinking about ourselves
- Falsely assumes that our lives are separate
- Death is usually “death in the family.”
- Need to consider that relational context. Often medical ethics discussions about death does not do so
when would someone be better off dead?
point 1: pain not the only reason
point 2: sometimes can be better off dead even if you don’t have a terminal illness
reasons to be better off dead
- severe and unrelieved pain
- permanent unconsciousness
- severe dementia
- physical disability
- progressive/continuous deterioration
- lose of independence/dehumanization
- notice that these are not all of these involve standard physical pain
dying as a relief
- terminal illness is not the only situation in which one is better off dead
- it might be worse to not have a terminal illness. consider case of progressive dementia
- refusing medical treatment does not always create a reasonably good death
religion and ending life
- it is wrong to end life before God chooses to end it
- assumption: life is God’s gift to give/take away
- all suicide (even mercy killing) ends a life before God chooses it
- Therefore, all suicide is wrong
objection 1
should work both ways
objection 1: should work both ways
- If it is possible to die sooner than God wants, it should be possible to die later than God wants
- If the reply is “everyone dies at the right time ordained by God,” then a suicide would be the right time
Objection 2
God’s “Right Time” might involve suicide
objection 2: god’s “right time” might involve suicide
“ . . . .we have no right to assume that God will ‘take my life’ when it is the right time for me to die. There could be a religious test—God may want me to take my own life and question whether I will meet this final challenge” (p. 684).
main argument about WHO has a duty to die
- i have special obligations to loved ones (especially family)
- these special obligations may require me to sacrifice my own interests in ways other obligations don’t - i shouldn’t impose severe burdens on my loved ones
- if prolonging my life does impose severe burdens, then i ought (have a duty to) not prolong my life (i should die)
- the duty to die is prima-facie
- the conclusion is influenced by a number of conditions which strengthen or weaken the duty (the WHEN question)
WHEN is the duty to die stronger?
- The greater the burdens you impose.
- Your loved ones are having a hard life.
- Loved ones have sacrificed for YOU.
- You have already lived a good, full life.
- You are older and have less life to live.
- You cannot adjust to your illness or handicap.
- The part of you that is loved will soon be gone.
Who should kill me?
myself, my family, doctors
unassisted suicide: i should kill myself
- I am responsible for my own life, especially the most important matters like whether to continue to live or die.
- It is unreasonable for me to ask others to perform actions that I am most responsible for.
- It is unreasonable to impose the burden of killing me on others.
- Therefore, I should kill myself.
5 reasons why killing myself is not optimal
- many people, especially the very sick, are physically unable
- not always so easy to “pull the trigger”
- risk of failed suicide attempt resulting in permanent damage
- might take life earlier than necessary
- isolated approach to suicide that does not include family