Final Exam Flashcards
Epistemically justified
If a belief is good within a relevant category of evaluation
Martin’s connection between justification and argument?
for a belief that p to be justified, one must be able to justify that belief/give a good argument for its truth
Examples challenging Martins’ connection between justification and need for arguments
3 year old could have a belief but is unable to justify it, like they saw a deer in the backyard; even if can’t say what it is based on, it’s still justified
1 plus 1 = 2 (we dont’ have a good argument for it, but seems to be true)
General reliability of cognitive faculties
What is the regress/Pyrrhonian problematic?
Caused by Martin’s connection between justification and argument
Seems that P’s being argumentativtively based on Q can confer justification on P only if Q is justified, but this means that fully accounting of rate justification of P will require that we then proceed to give an account of the justification of Q - leads to either infinite chain, circular chain, or chain with a starting point
What are the three options for the regress problem
Infinite chain
Circular chain
Chain w/ starting point
Infinitism implications and objections
Need infinite string of arguments involving different propositions, also would need argument just for infinite number of propositions; maybe impossible
Coherentism implications and objections
Beliefs justified in virtue of being part of a coherent system of beliefs (circular chain insufficient on account of question begging)
Foundationalism implications and objections
Some beliefs are properly basic; they are not justified in virtue of being based on other justified beliefs, but for some other reason; other claims justified in virtue of being conclusion of an inferential chain terminating in proper basic beliefs; do not need inferential support to be justified; criticized for being too dogmatic
Basic belief
A belief that is accepted without being based on other beliefs that one holds, for example “I am seeing a tree”; contrasts with derived beliefs
Properly basic belief
rationally justified and appropriate for a person to accept that belief in a basic way
If she religious beliefs are properly basic, then…
the question of whether religious beliefs are justified will not come down to whether there are good arguments for religious belief
Evidentialism:
justified religious belief must be based on evidence that is,, in principle, publicly available and dialectically effective
Reformed epistimology
religious beliefs could be properly basic, justified without argumentative support
What are two types of non-evidentialism
Reformed epistemology and pragmatism
Examples of religious experience
answered or unanswered prayers
apparent miracles
perceptual experiences (appearance that is relevantly analoguous to sense perception)
experiences of insight (in worship, epiphany, meditaiton)
What does James say on the noetic quality of mystical experience
The insightful character of mystical experiences; unlike mere visual perception, mystical experience purports to bring some sort of cognitive improvement or deeper understanding (deeper significance is appreciate)
Catch with James’ noetic quality of mystical experience
For mystical insight to have philosophical experience, it must be integrated into a theory informed by more standard philosophical reasoning
Contrast between noetic and purely perceptual mystical experiences
Noetic gives you new insights/ways of understanding
Affective rationalism:
Proper affective responses/emotionally engaged experiences can play a crucial role in facilitating rational insight into the plausibility of some position; these insightful experiences could increase rational probability; but still emphasizes rational assessment x
What is the argument with affective rationalism
- appropriate affective response arguably crucial to facilitating isngihtt into moral and value claims
- Traditional theism relies on claims that a good God is responsible of world, so our assessment of theism will depend on worthiness judgments (could a world like ours be worthy of creation by a good god?)
- Cannot assess these claims dispassionately
Example of when affective rationalism comes into handy
Unable to assess power of responsibility theodicy without assessing how valuable mutal responsibility is, and if it is valuable to the level that would warrant God doing that even though it could cause pain
What might Martin-style critiques of experience-based grounds for religious belief imply and then the rejoined?
- Suggest that primary way religious experience might help ground religious belief is by providing material for an inference to the best explanation; but in reality religious experience might give someone a new and meaningful way of shaping the world that shapes the apparent plausibility of religious outlooks
Alston’s perceptual model of experience-based religious belief
There is an apparent perceptual experience of God, and this experience is the justifying ground for belief in the existence of the perceived reality; most beliefs formed by sense perception are justified non-inferentiallly
Alston’s thesis
If God exists, then many religious experiences could be genuinely counted as cases of perceiving god
Alstons’ analogy:
going from a mystical experience to the conclusion that God exists isn’t any different from going from sense perception to conclusion that something exists
Defeaters
just because properly basic beliefs start off juried doesn’t mean they cannot lose this justification
Two examples of defeaters and explanations
Rebutting defeater (evidence that p is false)
Undercutting defeater (undercuts basis for believing p - untrustworthy source)
How does Alston say we can establish ultima facie justification
Need to show prima faciejsutificaiotn can survive undercutting defeaters
What is a potential undercutting defeater for those beliefs based on religious “perception?”
Martins’ Negative principle of credulity: the seeming absence of God is as powerful “perceptual” justification as the putative appearance of God
Does Platinga prioritize sense perceptual beliefs among non=inferentially justified beliefs we might have?
No - perception shouldn’t be the paradigm for religious belief
Why does Plating dislike classical foundationalist conception of proper basicality (2)
- It would require many paradigmatically reasonable beliefs to be dismissed as unjustified (belief in the reality of a long past, belief that other people are conscious)
- Self-undermining
What does classical foundationalism admit as properly basic
- self-evident (a priori, math/logical truths)
- incorrigible (my toe is in pain)
- evident to the sense
What is Platinga’s view of a warranted belief?
A belief that comes from truth-oriented properly functioning faculties; if theism is true and God exists, then belief sin God are probably the result of truth-aimed proper cognitive faulcites.
Great Pumpking Objection
Structurally similar to proper functionalist account could be used to justify this; also why is Great Pumpkin not basic belief?
What is Plantinga’s alternative to classical foundationalism as whether holding a belief is warranted?
Proper functionalist account of warrant: Belief B on the part of a subject as warrant if and only if that belief is a result of the subject’s faculties functioning properly in an appropriate environment according to got a design plan that successfully aims at truth acquisition
Implications of proper functionalist account?
If this is true and God exists, then makes sense to think God would design us so that theistic belief was natural
Response to Great Pumpkins Objection from reformed epistemologists:
no reason to expect that the correct philosophical account of rationality/warrant will provide us ways to distinguish between silly and respectable views (if it did, it might lead to classical foundationalism with skeptical results); might have to look at world and base it off of that (in a world w/ very reliable dreams, our belief that we’re awake is not as justified as in a world w/out very reliable dreams)
Pragmatism
religious belief might be rationally based on practical reasons that do not ear on truth or probability of religious belief, but instead on question of whether it would be in some way good or advantageous to have the belief in question
Practical/pragmatic reasons
reasons that support the conclusion “it would be good to believe p” but that do not support the conclusion “p”
What are three types of pragmatic arguments for religious belief?
Prudential
Moral
Existential
Prudential pragmatic arguments
Faith is instrumental for a good we have (Pascal for happiness)
Moral pragmatic arguments
Our confidence in objective reality of moral life rationally requires faith (Kant)
Existential pragmatic arguments
Faith not just instrumental to some goal, but is in some sense consitituve of the kind of person or way of life that is most excellent, noble, or beautiful
Utility of Pascal’s wager?
Expected utility of Wager exceeds expected utility of not wagering as long as the probability of “god exists” is some positive finite number
what does Pascal suggest if you can’t cause the belief?
Take actions that might lead to that
Possible objections to Pascal’s wager
Other gods/jealous gods objection
Calculating
Problems with “infinite utilities”
Jealous Gods objection
By wagering for one God, maybe you wager against another; maybe some Gods less rewarding than others
Calculating objection
Maybe God will punish you for doing utilitarian calculation
Problem with infinite utilities
Uncertainty regarding which actions really count as wagering on God
in what way does Kirkegaard appeal to faith?
Not as something we have, but rather as most desirable way to be human
Objective truth
Right conception of reality; obtained by believing true propositions
subjective truth
Right relation to reality; obtained by living in a humanly excellent way
What is necessary for passion, in Kirkegaard’s opinion?
Thinking uncertainty