Ethics Glossary Flashcards
Agency
The capacity of an agent to act in any given environment.
Agent
A being who is capable of action. Agency and action are typically restricted to human beings, because human beings have the capacity to reason, make a choice between two courses of action, then do what they’ve chosen.
A priori
A Latin term that usually describes a belief (or knowledge) that is known prior to or independently from experience. A priori beliefs are contrasted with a posteriori beliefs, which are ones derived from experience.
Argument
An argument is a series of propositions intended to support a conclusion. The propositions offered in support of the conclusion are termed premises.
Autonomy
(from the Greek auto — self, and nomos — law) An agent has autonomy insofar as it is rational and free. For Kant, moral autonomy was only achieved through following the categorical imperative.
Cognitivism and non—cognitivism
Cognitivism in ethics is the View that moral judgements are propositions which can be known —- they refer to the world and they have a truth- value (they are capable of being true or false). Non-cognitivism is the View that moral judgements cannot be known, because they do not say anything true or false about the world (they do not have a truth—value). There are many different forms of non-cognitivism such as emotivism, prescriptivism and nihilism. See also realism and anti—realism.
Conclusion
A belief or statement that an argument tries to prove. If an argument is valid and all of the premises are true, then the conclusion will also be true.
Consequentialist ethics
A type of normative moral theory which views the moral value of an action as lying in its consequences. So an action is judged to be good if it brings about beneficial consequences, and bad if it brings about harmful ones. This is in contrast to deontology. Egoism and utilitarianism are two examples of consequentialism.
Deontological ethics
A type of normative moral theory which views the moral value of an action as lying in the action itself. So an action is right or wrong in itself, whatever the consequences. Generally, deontologists (such as Kant) propose certain rules or principles that guide us as to which actions are right and which are wrong. This is in contrast to consequentialism. Divine command ethics and Kantian ethics are two examples of deontological theories.
Disposition
Our tendency to behave in certain ways, our character traits. This term is used by virtue ethicists, who believe we ought to develop virtuous dispositions.
Divine command ethics
A type of deontological ethical theory, which claims that the moral value of an action is determined by the commands of God. So an action is right if it follows one of God’s commands.
Duty
An action which we are required or impelled to carry out. Kant’s deontological theory places duty at its centre. For Kant, duties are experienced as imperatives. See also prima facie duties.
Emotivism/emotivist
A non-cognitivist theory of the meaning of moral terms and judgements. In its basic form, emotivism claims that moral judgements do not refer to anything in the world, but are expressions of feelings of approval or disapproval.
Empirical fact
A fact established by observation.
Empiricism/empiricist
The claim that our beliefs and knowledge must be based on experience.
Eudaimonia
According to many ancient Greek philosophers eudaimonia is the goal or ‘good’ we are all striving for. Sometimes translated as ‘happiness’, it is probably closer in meaning to ‘flourishing’. Aristotle’s virtue ethics is centred around eudaimonia.
Fallacy
This refers to an argument which has gone wrong, either because a mistake has been made, rendering the argument invalid; or because the argument has a form, or structure, which is always invalid (see also the
naturalistic fallacy).
Golden rule
Versions of this rule have been proposed at various points within religion and moral philosophy (e.g. by Confucius, Jesus, Hobbes and Kant). The basic idea is that we should be impartial, and not afford ourselves special treatment: we should treat others as we should like to be treated. See also universalisability.
Good
Actions are good according to whether they bring about certain positive outcomes — these may be pleasure or happiness, or something more intangible (Moore believed that love of friendship and beauty were goods). Consequentialists believe that moral value lies in the good (or bad) consequences of an action. But ‘good’ also has a functional meaning, in the sense that ‘good’ means ‘fulfilling your function well’. Aristotle believed that we had a function and hence could be good in both senses: by being good (fulfilling our function) we could reach the good (eudaimonia).
Hedonism/hedonistic
The claim that pleasure is the good. Many utilitarians are hedonists, in that they believe we ought to try to maximise pleasure (for the majority).
Imperative
In Kantian ethics we experience our duties as commands (imperatives) which are categorical, or absolute. These categorical imperatives are commands that we are obliged to follow no matter what, and according to Kant only these are moral imperatives. As rational agents we can work out the categorical imperative by asking whether the maxim that lies behind our action is universalisable. Other imperatives, things we should do in order to achieve some goal, are conditional or hypothetical imperatives, and they are not moral according to Kant.
Intuitionism/intuitionist
A realist theory which claims that we can determine what is right or good according to our moral intuitions. For intuitionists, the terms ‘right’ and ‘good’ do refer to something objective, but they cannot be reduced to naturalistic terms.