Discussions Flashcards

1
Q

Economists see pollution problems as examples of the class of adverse externality phenomena. An
adverse externality is said to occur when the decisions of one agent harm another in an unintended
way, and when no compensation occurs. Does this mean that if a pollution source, such as a power
station, compensates those affected by its emissions, then there is no pollution problem? Please
justify your response.

A

This depends on what you mean by a “pollution problem”. In general, even if compensation were paid, then som emissions will still take place, and so some “pollution” will continue. However, economist tend to use the phrase “pollution problem” to refer not to the existence of pollution as such, but to describe a level of pollution that is economically inefficient. If compensation is paid to all adcersely affected parties, that compensation properly compensates thos induviduals for the damage inflicted on them, and the firm paying the compensation adjusts its behavior optimally taking into consideration the copensation payable, then the post-compensation situation will be economically efficient, and so not a pollution problem. Notice, incidentally, that the economic efficiency criterion implies that too few emission can be a “problem”, not only too many emissions.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
2
Q

Discuss the differences between the following mechanisms:

- Pareto criterion.
- Kaldor-Hicks criterion.

Give an example of an application of the Kaldor-Hicks criterion and explain why such a criterion is
regarded as an expression of cost-benefit analysis.

A

Definiton of the following mechanisms

Pareto criterion, also known as Pareto efficiency or pareto optimality. It states that en allocation of ressources, is efficient if it is not possible to make one or more persons better off without making at least one other person worse off. Where gains are possible without anyone else suffering, trades will occur until al such gains have been made. These gains are known as pareto improvements. When all susch gains have been made, the resulting allocation is reffered to as pereto optiaml or Pareto efficient.

The Kaldo-Hicks citerion extends the Pareto crieterion by introducing the possibility of compensation or transfers amongst individuals. The test states that a reallocation is desirable if

- The winners compensate the losers and still be better off. 

In this case the winners are not required to compensate the other, only that it is possible for them to do so.

Some similarities and differences between the two criteria

Similarities:

- Neither criterion take into account the fairness of the distribution of well being (although weighting can be applied)

Differences

- The pareto criterion cannot be used for the majority of proposed reallocations as most policies will result in individuals gaining or loosing. 
- Not everyone is better of under the Kaldor Hicks criterions - Pareto efficiency requires making every party involved better of (or at least not worse off). The Kaldor-Hicks criterion does not require that the compensation actually take place, only that it is possible to do so. A more efficient outcome can in fact leave some people worse off. It is a separate matter for government to decide wether compensation should occur and arrange for it. 
- Every pareto improvement is a Kaldor Hicks improvement, most Kaldor Hicks improvenments are not pareto improvements.

Example:

Scenario: Imagine a new factory opens in a town.

Winners: The factory provides jobs and boosts the local economy.
Losers: The factory causes pollution that affects some residents' health.

Kaldor-Hicks Evaluation: The factory opening is considered efficient if the economic gains (profits, wages, economic growth) are large enough that the winners could, in theory, compensate the losers (those affected by pollution) and still have some benefits left over.

In cost-benefit analysis, economist work with monetary meassures which are intended to measure utility changes. A project is evaluated by comparing the total costs with the total benefits. It will be approved if the benefits exceed the costs.

This is effectively an application of the Kaldor-Hicks criterion because it is equivalent to requiring that the benefits be enough that those that benefit could in theory compensate those that have lose and still the winners would get a small profit.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
3
Q

Does international trade harm the environment?

A

A natural starting point for answering this question is to
restate the so-called Pollution Haven Hypothesis (PHH)
which comes in two versions.

  • First version: Liberalization of trade or foreign investment
    causes pollution-intensive activities to relocate to countries
    with weaker environmental quality.
  • Second version: Tightening pollution policy in one country
    causes pollution-intensive activities to relocate to other
    countries with weaker environmental policy.

In the curriculum, the validity of the first version of PHH is
analyzed in a model where the world economy is divided
into a rich Northern region and a poorer Southern region.
* Each region produces two tradable goods, a capital-
intensive good and a labour-intensive good. Pollution can be
seen as an input in production in the sense that allowing
higher emissions enables firms to increase their outputs. The
governments in both regions impose an emissions tax in
order to reduce emissions, since pollution harms consumer
welfare.

At any given pollution tax rate, production of a unit of the
capital-intensive good generates more pollution than
production of a unit of the labour-intensive good.
* Before trade is liberalized, the North has a higher pollution
tax rate than the South, because consumer (voter) demand
for environmental protection is an increasing function of
income, and income per capita is higher in the North than in
the South.

When trade in goods is liberalized, the lower pollution tax
rate tends to give the Southern region a comparative
advantage in the production of the pollution-intensive
capital-intensive good, thereby tending to shift some of the
world production of this good in the direction of the South,
as predicted by the first version of the PHH.
* But since rich countries are generally more capital-
abundant, the higher capital/labour ratio in the rich North
tends to give the Northern region a comparative advantage
in production of the capital-intensive “dirty” good (seen in
isolation), thereby offsetting the comparative disadvantage
arising from the relatively high pollution tax rate.

  • Depending on the net effect of these offsetting impacts on
    comparative advantage, trade liberalization can either shift
    some of the production of the dirty good in the direction of
    the South or in the direction of the North.
  • If the North ends up with a higher share of world production
    of the capital-intensive dirty good, the total global emissions
    will go down, because some of the world production of the
    pollution-intensive good is shifted to a region with stricter
    environmental regulation. This will happen if the North is
    very capital-abundant and/or if the North is not “too much”
    richer than the South and hence does not have a much
    higher pollution tax rate.

This scenario shows that the Pollution Haven Hypothesis is
not necessarily correct from a theoretical viewpoint.
* => It is an empirical question whether the PHH holds.
* Empirical evidence suggests that when it comes to CO2-
emissions, the trade liberalization in recent decades has
tended to shift some of the global emissions to the new
emerging market economies, particularly China, which is in
line with the PHH.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
4
Q

A good answer to “Does international trade harm the
environments?” could also talk about what ?

A

Mention that environmental policy (the permitted level
of pollution) can be used strategically by governments
in an effort to shift profits from foreign to domestic
firms operating in the same international market under
conditions of imperfect competition.

Finally, an answer may include a reference to the Porter
Hypothesis which comes in a “weak” and in a “strong”
version.
* The weak version says that the direct static effects of
environmental regulation on domestic production costs may
be partly offset by induced technical progress and
elimination of unnecessary waste, as firms are induced to
find new ways of reducing their emissions.
* The strong version of the Porter hypothesis says that
environmental regulation may actually improve the
international competiveness of domestic firms by making
them more innovative.

In both versions of the Porter
Hypothesis environmental regulation is assumed to be
“intelligent”, meaning that it is flexible and oriented
towards the use of cost-effective market-based policy
instruments like emission taxes or tradable emission
permits.
* The empirical evidence has given some support to the weak
version of the Porter Hypothesis, but not to the strong
version.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
5
Q

We argued that Rawls’s Difference Principle asserts that it is only just to
have an unequal distribution of wealth if all persons benefit from that allocation, relative to the
situation of an equal distribution. But we also argued that the total level of utility attainable might
depend on the distribution of wealth, as utility could be higher in an unequal position if incentive
effects enhance productive efficiency.

Discuss the implications of these comments for a
morally just distribution of resources within and between
countries.

A

Rawl´s notion of justice imply that i can only be just that we have unequal distribution of resources within and between countries if all induviduals is more wealthy (Pareto improvement) then they would be in the case of equal distribution.

On the other hand we also argued that if the “total level of utility” within and between countries are higher in the case of unequal destribution it would be morally just, but notice that this is not the same as in the Rawlsian case. This is a typical utilitarian stance, where the total level of well being matters, but not its distribution. The theory accept that some people get an extremly high utility and others get a low, if the average is better than in the equal case. Still all people could be better off (Paerto improvement) if the society or government introduce a way of redestributing the wealth.

If we look at the world we could argue that is has taken a utilitarian stance within the countries but not between. In general the worlds country become more equal, but within the country we see greater unequality. Utilitarians will argue this is just, where Rawlsians will argue for it is not just.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
6
Q

Consider recycling. How does recycling substitute
for environmental functions?

A

Substituting man-made capital services
for environmental services: Examples

  • The waste sink function:
    – Treatment of discharge of sewage into a river– the
    demand made upon the assimilative capacity is
    reduced for a given level of sewage.
    – Capital in the form of a sewage treatment plant substitutes
    for the natural environmental function of waste sink to an
    extent dependent on the level of treatment that the plant
    provides.
  • Energy conservation: Involves substitution of capital
    for the use of (additional) energy inputs from the
    natural resource base.
  • Amenity services: provision by physical capital may
    yield substitutes in some dimensions (e.g., swimming
    in a pool versus swimming in a lake)
  • Life support services: very limited substitution
    possibilities
    – The quantity of human life that could be sustained
    in the absence of natural life-support functions is
    quite small.
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
7
Q

What are some pros and cons with the measure of
ecological footprint?

A

The ecological footprint is a measure that evaluates the environmental impact of human activities in terms of the amount of biologically productive land and water area required to produce the resources consumed and to assimilate the wastes generated. Important: The footprint size will vary with technology as
well as with levels and patterns of production and
consumption. Here are some pros and cons of using this measure:

Chatten:

Most Important Pros

Comprehensive Overview: The ecological footprint provides a broad measure that captures various aspects of human consumption and waste, offering a clear and understandable picture of overall environmental impact. This holistic approach is valuable for understanding the full extent of human activities on the environment.

Awareness and Education: It raises awareness among individuals, organizations, and governments about their ecological impact. This heightened awareness can lead to more sustainable practices and policies, driving collective action towards reducing ecological footprints.

Policy Development: The ecological footprint is a useful tool for policymakers, helping them design and implement strategies to reduce environmental impacts. By providing clear and actionable data, it supports the development of effective sustainability policies.

Most Important Cons

Data Limitations: The accuracy of the ecological footprint measure depends on the availability and reliability of data. Inconsistencies and gaps in data can lead to inaccurate assessments, which can undermine the effectiveness of the measure.

Simplification: The ecological footprint may oversimplify complex environmental issues, failing to capture the full range of ecological impacts and interactions. This can lead to an incomplete understanding of environmental sustainability and potentially misguided decisions.

Ignores Social and Economic Factors: The measure does not account for social and economic factors that influence resource use and sustainability, such as income distribution, technological advancements, and cultural practices. This limitation can result in an incomplete picture of sustainability and overlook important drivers of environmental impact.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
8
Q

How would you formalize growth and development
in a production function?

A

Production function:

Q = TFPxf(g(K,L),M)

where
Q= output,
M= materials,
K= capital stock, L= labour,
TFP= total factor productivity

According to ecological economists, M and g(K,L) tend to move together

“Growth” = rise in Q achieved through rise in f (*): requires increase in M

“Development” = rise in Q achieved through rise in TFP without an increase in M

Points of agreement

  • Ecological economists do not object to growth
    achieved through a rise in TFP (“development”)
  • Many environmental economists acknowledge that
    human-made capital can only substitute for natural
    capital as long as the vital life-support services of
    the environment is not threatened
  • Broad agreement that resource productivity Q/M
    must be increased to achieve sustainability
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
9
Q

What role should rights, duties or obligations play, in your
opinion, when chosing environmental targets or policy?

A

Integration in Policy-Making

Equity and Justice: Policies should be designed to ensure that the benefits and burdens of environmental actions are shared equitably. This means protecting vulnerable populations from disproportionate environmental harm and ensuring that everyone has access to the benefits of a healthy environment.

Accountability: Clear rights, duties, and obligations create a framework for accountability. Governments, businesses, and individuals can be held accountable for their actions, ensuring that commitments to environmental protection are met.

Holistic Approach: Considering rights, duties, and obligations ensures a holistic approach to environmental policy-making. It balances the need for economic development with the necessity of protecting the environment and upholding social justice.

From this I could decide what is important for me, political and cultural.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
10
Q

Discuss the statement “Only the highest standards of
environmental purity will do.

A

The statement “Only the highest standards of environmental purity will do” reflects a strong commitment to sustainability, but practical implications and trade-offs must be considered. Here are key points:

Advantages

Long-Term Sustainability: High standards preserve natural resources and biodiversity, ensuring ecosystems’ health.
Health Benefits: Reducing pollution improves public health and reduces healthcare costs.
Innovation: High standards drive advancements in green technologies, fostering innovation and leadership in sustainability.

Challenges

Economic Costs: Implementing the highest standards can be expensive, impacting businesses and economic growth.
Feasibility and Trade-Offs: Balancing high environmental standards with practical economic and social considerations can be challenging. Not all regions or industries may be able to achieve these standards without significant trade-offs.
Balanced Approach
Adaptive Standards: Flexible and gradual implementation allows for continuous improvement without imposing undue burdens.
Stakeholder Involvement: Engaging businesses, communities, and governments ensures realistic and equitable standards, promoting widespread support.

Conclusion
While aiming for the highest environmental standards is vital for sustainability, it must be balanced with economic and social realities. A flexible, inclusive approach can achieve significant progress while addressing diverse needs and challenges.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
11
Q

Can you think of other objectives or goals of pollution policy?

A

We conclude by returning to an issue addressed at the outset:
The objectives of pollution policy.
* Throughout most of these lecture a single criterion,
economic efficiency, has been adopted.
* But it would be wrong to assume that this is, or should be, the
only or even the main objective.
* Each of the following has some claim to be regarded as a goal of
environmental policy, and so might be given some weight in
determining pollution targets:
– Sustainability and ecological goals (e.g. minimum disruption to
ecosystems, maintenance of biodiversity)
– Human health protection as the overriding goal
– Public preferences (e.g. distributional goals)

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
12
Q

Is cost-effectiveness in conflict with any of the other criteria
for selecting pollution control instruments?

A

Cost-effectiveness is a key criterion in selecting pollution control instruments, but it can sometimes conflict with other important criteria. Here are some potential conflicts and how they might be addressed:

Environmental Effectiveness
Conflict: Cost-effective measures might not always achieve the desired level of environmental protection. For instance, cheaper solutions may not sufficiently reduce pollution to meet environmental standards.
Resolution: Ensure that cost-effective solutions are also environmentally effective by setting minimum performance standards and combining various measures to achieve comprehensive protection.
Equity and Fairness
Conflict: Cost-effective measures may disproportionately affect certain populations. For example, pollution taxes could be regressive, impacting lower-income groups more significantly.
Resolution: Implement complementary policies, such as subsidies or rebates for low-income households, to offset the regressive impacts and ensure a fair distribution of costs and benefits.
Political and Public Acceptability
Conflict: The most cost-effective measures may face political resistance or lack public support. For example, carbon taxes are cost-effective but often unpopular.
Resolution: Engage in public consultation and education to build support for cost-effective measures. Consider phased implementation or combining with other popular policies to increase acceptability.
Administrative Feasibility
Conflict: Cost-effective measures might be complex to administer, requiring sophisticated monitoring and enforcement mechanisms.
Resolution: Simplify administrative processes where possible and invest in capacity building for effective implementation. Ensure that the chosen instruments are practical and manageable within the existing administrative framework.
Technological Innovation
Conflict: Focusing solely on cost-effectiveness might discourage investment in innovative but initially expensive technologies.
Resolution: Design policies that also incentivize innovation, such as providing subsidies for research and development or implementing flexible regulations that allow for technological advancements.
Summary
Cost-effectiveness is crucial but must be balanced with environmental effectiveness, equity, acceptability, administrative feasibility, and technological innovation. By considering these criteria together, policymakers can design pollution control instruments that are not only cost-effective but also fair, effective, and sustainable.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
13
Q

On your view, when can institutional approaches to facilitate
internalisation of externalities, such as facilitation of
bargaining, specification of liability, or development of social
responsibility be successful?

A

Institutional approaches to facilitate the internalization of externalities can be successful when specific conditions and factors are met. Here’s an overview of when such approaches can be effective:

Facilitation of Bargaining (Coase Theorem)
Clear Property Rights: Successful bargaining requires well-defined and enforceable property rights so that parties can negotiate over the allocation of resources or responsibilities.
Low Transaction Costs: For bargaining to be practical, transaction costs (e.g., costs of negotiating, enforcing agreements) must be low. This is more feasible in smaller, less complex settings.
Small Number of Parties: Bargaining is more likely to be successful when fewer parties are involved, making it easier to reach agreements.
Mutual Benefit: Both parties must see a clear benefit from the negotiation and agreement.
Specification of Liability
Clear Legal Framework: A robust legal system must clearly define and enforce liability rules, ensuring that polluters are held accountable for the harm they cause.
Effective Enforcement: Regulatory agencies must have the capacity to monitor compliance and enforce penalties for violations.
Economic Incentives: Liability rules should create economic incentives for polluters to reduce emissions or invest in cleaner technologies.
Public Awareness: Stakeholders must be aware of their rights and the mechanisms available to seek compensation for environmental damages.
Development of Social Responsibility
Corporate Culture: Companies need to cultivate a corporate culture that values sustainability and ethical behavior, integrating social responsibility into their core operations.
Stakeholder Engagement: Businesses should actively engage with stakeholders, including customers, employees, and communities, to align their practices with societal expectations.
Transparency and Reporting: Regular, transparent reporting on environmental performance can build trust and accountability, encouraging companies to internalize externalities.
Market Incentives: Consumers and investors increasingly prefer companies with strong social responsibility practices, providing market incentives for businesses to adopt sustainable practices.
Regulatory Support: Government policies that support and incentivize corporate social responsibility (e.g., tax benefits, recognition programs) can enhance the effectiveness of these approaches.
General Conditions for Success
Public Awareness and Support: Broad public awareness and support for environmental protection can drive the success of these approaches. Educated and engaged citizens can exert pressure on businesses and policymakers.
Strong Institutions: Effective institutions are crucial for implementing and enforcing rules, facilitating bargaining, and supporting social responsibility initiatives.
Collaboration and Partnerships: Collaboration between government, industry, and civil society can enhance the effectiveness of institutional approaches by pooling resources and expertise.
Adaptability and Flexibility: Institutional approaches should be adaptable to changing circumstances and flexible enough to address new challenges and opportunities in environmental management.
Conclusion
Institutional approaches to internalizing externalities can be successful when there is a clear legal framework, effective enforcement, low transaction costs, and strong stakeholder engagement. The right mix of public awareness, corporate culture, regulatory support, and collaboration is essential for these approaches to achieve their desired outcomes.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
14
Q

Suppose instead of a tax that we subsidise abatement and that the target is given.
* What would the regulator need to know?
* As compared to taxing emissions, would anything change?

A

To attain ANY specific emissions target using a tax or subsidy instrument, knowledge of the aggregate (pre-tax or pre-subsidy) marginal benefit of emissions function (the MAC curve) would be sufficient.

  • For ANY emission abatement subsidy (or emission tax) rate, some –
    probably unknown – amount of emissions reduction would be
    obtained.
  • However, as all controlled profit-maximising firms will reduce
    emissions up to the point where marginal abatement costs are brought
    into equality with this subsidy (or tax) rate, marginal abatement costs
    are equalised and so emissions reduction is achieved at least cost.
  • Whatever level of abatement is generated would be attained at
    minimum feasible cost. Subsidies (and taxes by an equivalent argument) are, therefore, cost-
    efficient policy instruments.

An emissions tax and an emissions abatement subsidy (at the same rate)
differ in terms of the distribution of gains and losses. This has important
implications for the political acceptability and the political feasibility of the
instruments. It also could affect the long-run level of pollution abatement
under some circumstances, via alteration of the size of the industry.

E.g. a subsidy to firms with higher abatement would increase their profit. This would in the general competitive market theory mean that more firms enter the market until the profit is zero. This would on the long term mean more firms and therefore a higher level of emissions. Thus subsidizing firms for abatement is not the best option on the long term. On the short term it could be feasible.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
15
Q

Discuss wether if it is a good assumption that efficiency-based pollution targets so far
assumed that the policy maker knows the relevant cost and benefit functions.

A

This assumption is often not plausible.

The EPA will often not know with certainty the costs and/ or benefits of
pollution:

  • Limited Information: The EPA often lacks complete information on the costs and benefits of pollution control measures. This uncertainty can stem from insufficient data, evolving technologies, and unpredictable economic impacts.
    Dynamic and Complex Systems: Environmental and economic systems are complex and dynamic. The costs and benefits of pollution control can change over time due to technological advancements, changes in economic conditions, and shifts in public preferences and behaviors.
  • Where non-convexities are present, it is not sufficient to know the
    values of such things near the current position of the economy; they
    have to be known across the whole range of possibilities.
  • For stock pollutants, stock effects and spatial considerations imply that
    the appropriate functions vary from place to place and from time to
    time and the EPA may not have full information on this.
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
16
Q

Suppose we sample data. What can be some issues with correctly
identifying costs and benefits?

A

Limited information and uncertainty arises from:

The costs involved in acquiring, validating and processing information,
implying that census-data (for the full population) are likely to be very
expensive.
* Sampling error, associated with the use of sampling methods and statistical
inference from the sample data: The sample may not be representative.
* The data collected may not properly represent what the investigator is seeking
to obtain.
– Abatement costs: Those who possess relevant information may have
incentives not to truthfully reveal it.
* Difficulties in indentifying and evaluating the benefits of pollution abatement .
– Scientific knowledge about pollution impacts is far from complete.
– Valuation of environmental services is also difficult, and there is little
consensus about the validity of current valuation techniques.

Some methodological issues

Relevant costs and prices (for both benefit and cost estimation)
needed for evaluation should be those that correspond to a socially
efficient outcome:
- These may bear little relation to observed costs and prices where
the economy is a long way from that optimum.
* Difficulties are compounded by ‘second-best’ considerations: If some
non-environmental market failures are impossible to correct, the
“first-best” environmental policy may not be socially optimal.
* => Limited information and uncertainty do not mean that decisions
should be taken in the same way (but have less ‘accuracy’) as under
conditions of full information.

17
Q

Suppose the climate problem being represented by linear MAC and
MD curves, where we are unsure about the location of the MAC
curve.
* If you could choose only one instrument, would you recommend
price or quantity regulation?

A

Once the existence of non-linearity or threshold effects is admitted,
general results are harder to find.
* => In some circumstances at least, combined tax–quantity-
control programmes may have attractive properties.
* The presence of uncertainty substantially weakens the general
presumption in favour of incentive-based instruments over
quantitative regulations.
* These may be better in some circumstances but not in all.

18
Q

How can we get the firms to tell the truth about their MACs, if they have more information than the regulator?

A

Kwerel’s mechanism is designed to incentivize firms to reveal their true marginal abatement costs (MACs) by using a combination of regulatory instruments. The mechanism leverages economic incentives to align the interests of the firms with truthful reporting. Here’s how it works:

Understanding Kwerel’s Mechanism
Kwerel’s mechanism involves a two-part process:

Tax or Subsidy Scheme: Firms are subject to a tax or subsidy based on their reported abatement costs.
Market for Permits: Firms participate in a market where they can buy and sell permits for pollution, with the price of permits being determined by the market.
Steps of Kwerel’s Mechanism
Initial Allocation of Permits: The regulator allocates pollution permits to firms based on an initial estimate of their abatement costs or historical emissions levels.
Reporting Phase: Firms report their MACs to the regulator. The reported MACs influence the amount of tax or subsidy they receive.
Market Trading: Firms can trade permits in a competitive market. Firms with lower abatement costs will sell permits, while those with higher abatement costs will buy permits.
Incentivizing Truthful Reporting
Linking Taxes/Subsidies to Reported MACs: The tax or subsidy is designed such that if a firm overstates its abatement costs, it will receive a lower number of permits (or higher tax), making it costly to hold on to excess permits. Conversely, if it understates its costs, it risks having to buy expensive permits from the market.
Market Discipline: The market for permits ensures that the price of permits reflects the true marginal cost of abatement across firms. If a firm misreports its MAC, it will face financial consequences in the market, either by paying more for permits or by selling them at a loss.
Revenue Neutrality: The system can be designed to be revenue-neutral by adjusting taxes and subsidies so that the total amount collected equals the total amount paid out. This reduces the net financial burden on firms, focusing on the efficiency of emissions reductions.
Example Scenario
Firm A: Has low MACs and reports truthfully. It will sell its excess permits in the market and gain financially.
Firm B: Has high MACs and reports truthfully. It will buy permits, but the cost will be offset by accurate tax/subsidy adjustments.
Firm C: Misreports its MACs to appear lower than they are. Initially, it receives fewer permits and has to buy more expensive permits from the market, incurring a loss. This discourages future misreporting.
Benefits and Challenges
Benefits:

Accuracy: Firms are incentivized to report their true MACs to avoid financial penalties.
Efficiency: The market for permits ensures that pollution reduction is achieved at the lowest overall cost.
Flexibility: Firms can choose the most cost-effective way to comply, either through internal abatement or trading.
Challenges:

Complexity: Implementing and monitoring the mechanism can be complex and require substantial administrative resources.
Market Conditions: The effectiveness depends on a well-functioning market for permits, which requires sufficient liquidity and transparency.
Initial Allocation: Fairly allocating initial permits and setting appropriate tax/subsidy levels can be challenging and politically sensitive.

Conclusion
Kwerel’s mechanism provides a structured way to incentivize firms to truthfully report their marginal abatement costs by leveraging economic incentives and market mechanisms. While it offers a promising approach to achieving efficient pollution control, its success depends on careful design and robust regulatory oversight.

19
Q

Find out what is meant by “adverse selection”, and why it can lead
to asymmetric information.
* Why can adverse selection make it difficult to regulate pollution
efficiently?

A

Adverse Selection

Adverse selection refers to a situation in which one party in a transaction has more or better information than the other party, leading to an inefficient market outcome. This term is commonly used in economics and insurance markets but can also apply to various other scenarios, including environmental regulation.

Why Adverse Selection Leads to Asymmetric Information

In the context of pollution regulation, adverse selection arises because firms typically have more detailed and accurate information about their pollution control costs (marginal abatement costs, or MACs) than the regulators. Firms may choose to misrepresent their costs to gain a regulatory or financial advantage.

Information Imbalance: Firms know their specific pollution levels, abatement costs, and technological capabilities better than regulators.
Incentives to Misreport: Firms may underreport their abatement capabilities or overstate their costs to avoid stringent regulations or to gain more permits and subsidies.

Challenges in Regulating Pollution Efficiently

Misallocation of Resources
Reduced Effectiveness of Market-Based Instruments
Policy Design Complications

e.g. Pollution Taxes: If firms overstate their abatement costs, pollution taxes may be set too low, failing to incentivize sufficient pollution reduction. Conversely, if taxes are set based on inflated costs, firms with genuine high costs may struggle financially.

20
Q

Can you think of environmental problems and how
decisions are “interdependent”?

A

Examples:
* Where pollution spills over national boundaries, expenditures by any
one country on pollution abatement will give benefits to others as well.
* If a country chooses to spend nothing on pollution control, it can
obtain benefits if others do so.

In general: The pay-off to doing pollution control depends not only on one’s own choice, but also on the choices of others.

21
Q

We have now detailed incentives to join the coalition.
What are some incentives to exit?

A

Reasons
- economic
- political
- Strategic

Exampels

Kyoto Protocol: Countries like the United States initially signed but did not ratify the Kyoto Protocol, and Canada withdrew later, citing economic burdens and the absence of commitments from major emitters like China and India.

Paris Agreement: The United States announced its intention to withdraw from the Paris Agreement in 2017 under the Trump administration, arguing that the deal disadvantaged American workers and economy. (Note: The U.S. rejoined under the Biden administration.)

22
Q
A

Positive Feedback Effects Accelerating Global Warming

  • Ice cap is melting effect
  • Permafrost is disepearing effect on methan in the ground
  • Forest Dieback and Fires effect
  • Ocean Warming and Reduced Carbon Absorption

Negative Feedback Effect Slowing Down Global Warming
Increased Plant Growth (CO2 Fertilization Effect):
Description: Higher levels of CO2 in the atmosphere can enhance plant growth, as CO2 is a critical component of photosynthesis.
Effect: Increased plant growth can lead to higher rates of CO2 uptake by vegetation, which can reduce the concentration of CO2 in the atmosphere, thereby slowing the rate of global warming.

23
Q

Can you think of some potential damages from a
significant rise in the global mean surface temperature?

A

The potential damages from a significant rise in GMST are manifold.
Examples:

  • Loss of agricultural output* (* In some countries global warming can actually stimulate agricultural production,
    at least up to a certain level.)
  • Discomfort and increased health risks from higher temperature in
    some places
  • Damages from more frequent extreme weather events like storms,
    flooding, extreme precipitation, etc.
  • Loss of land due to rising sea levels and desertification

Loss of forests, wildlife, and species

  • Carbonization and acidification of oceans with potentially catastrophic
    implications for many maritime ecosystems
  • Social unrest and destabilizing migration wawes as the damages will
    be unevenly distributed, with a tendency for poorer countries to be
    more severely hurt
24
Q

Does green energy
technologies have decreasing marginal productivity? Discuss

A

Diminishing Returns

Resource Constraints: As deployment increases, green energy technologies can face resource constraints that lead to diminishing returns. For example, the best sites for wind turbines (those with the strongest and most consistent winds) are developed first, leaving less optimal locations for later projects.
Integration Challenges: Integrating a high share of renewables into the grid can become more complex and costly over time. Issues such as grid stability, storage needs, and the intermittent nature of some renewable sources require increasingly sophisticated and expensive solutions.
Technological Limits: Each technology has physical and technical limits. For instance, solar panels have efficiency ceilings based on current materials and technology. As the efficiency approaches these limits, further improvements become incrementally smaller and more costly.

Counteracting Factors

Technological Innovation: Continuous advancements can counteract decreasing marginal productivity. Innovations in materials, manufacturing processes, and system designs can lead to breakthroughs that reset the curve of diminishing returns. For example, the development of more efficient photovoltaic cells or advanced wind turbine designs can enhance productivity.
Economies of Scale: As green energy technologies scale up, production costs often decrease, and efficiencies improve. Mass production, better supply chains, and economies of scale can mitigate the effects of diminishing returns. The cost reductions seen in solar PV and wind energy over the past decades illustrate this effect.
Learning Curves: The industry often experiences learning curves where initial investments lead to knowledge gains that reduce costs and improve productivity. As companies gain experience, they can optimize installation, operation, and maintenance processes, leading to better overall performance.

25
Q

Discuss wether It is a good or bad thing that we focus on CO_2 instead of GHG (green house gases)?

A

Focusing on CO2 vs. All GHGs: Good or Bad?
Arguments for Focusing on CO2

CO2 is the Major Contributor: Carbon dioxide (CO2) is the most significant greenhouse gas emitted by human activities, accounting for the majority of emissions from energy production, transportation, and industrial processes. Targeting CO2 can address a large portion of the problem.
Measurement and Tracking: CO2 emissions are relatively easier to measure and track compared to other greenhouse gases. This simplicity can facilitate the implementation and monitoring of policies.
Established Policies and Technologies: There are already well-established policies and technologies aimed at reducing CO2 emissions, such as carbon pricing, renewable energy deployment, and energy efficiency measures.
Arguments for Focusing on All GHGs

Cost-Efficiency: The slide indicates that abatement costs will be lower if strategies focus on all GHGs rather than just CO2. This is because different GHGs have different abatement costs and potentials. Including all GHGs allows for the most cost-effective reductions by targeting the lowest-cost opportunities first.
Broader Impact: Other GHGs, such as methane (CH4) and nitrous oxide (N2O), are more potent than CO2 in terms of their global warming potential (GWP). Addressing these gases can have a significant impact on mitigating climate change.
Comprehensive Coverage: Strategies that include all GHGs can address emissions from a wider range of sources and sectors. For instance, methane emissions from agriculture and waste management or nitrous oxide emissions from agricultural practices.

26
Q

Suppose policy follows from the SCC. For example
that the carbon tax is set equal to the SCC.

Consider the ethical implicaitons.

A

Social Cost of Carbon (SCC) equals the carbon tax:

The SCC is the social welfare loss from the emission of an extra ton of CO2,
measured in equivalent units of consumption (in “DKK”).

Summary of Ethical Considerations

Intergenerational Equity: Ensuring that future generations are not unfairly burdened by the costs of current emissions is a significant ethical consideration. This involves setting a carbon tax that reflects the true long-term damages of emissions, even if it requires current generations to bear higher costs.

Global Equity: Developing equitable global climate policies that consider the economic capabilities and vulnerabilities of different nations is crucial. Wealthier nations may need to support poorer nations through technology transfer and financial aid to implement effective carbon pricing mechanisms.

Responsibility and Precaution: Policymakers have an ethical responsibility to act urgently and effectively to mitigate emissions, considering both the immediate and long-term impacts of climate change. This includes adhering to the precautionary principle and taking proactive measures to prevent severe future damages.

Fair Resource Allocation: Policies must ensure that resource allocation for climate mitigation and adaptation is fair, particularly in regions with high population growth and greater vulnerability to climate impacts.

By carefully considering these ethical implications, policymakers can design carbon taxes and other climate policies that are not only economically efficient but also just and equitable.

27
Q

How would you critique IAMs? What are the limitations?

A

Integrated Assessment Models (IAM)

  1. The optimal climate policy in IAMs depends crucially on the
    discount rate about which there is great ethical controversy.
  2. Standard IAMs fail to account for the fact that environmental goods
    are likely to become scarcer in the future.
  3. Standard IAMs assume that the growth rate of total factor
    productivity is unaffected by climate change.
    4.The empirical basis for estimating the damage function in IAMs is
    weak since global warming above 3 degrees has not been observed for
    a long time.
    5.Standard IAMs do not capture the risk of catastrophic climate change
    that may occur beyond highly uncertain “tipping point” in the climate
    system.
28
Q

Suppose we allow capital to flow freely between the countries.
Would the results change?

Suppose governments can set policy in a strategic manner. Intuitively,
would that change the results?

A

Let’s briefly consider another formulation of the Pollution haven
hypothesis:
* Tightening of environmental policy in one country will cause
movement of countries with weak regulation, given the existence of
free trade

We cannot conclude what happens to world pollution on behalf of the Pollution haven
hypothesis
* But: Suppose lower costs follows from superior technology. Then it may be that pollution goes down
* Conclusion: Case for the Pollution haven hypothesis not obvious, and
ultimately empirical question.

29
Q

Should decisions about environmental policy be made on
the basis of Cost-Benefit Analysis?

A

Advantages of Using CBA in Environmental Policy

Economic efficiency
Resource Allocation: CBA helps in allocating resources efficiently by comparing implementation costs against derived benefits.
Prioritization: It allows prioritizing environmental projects that provide the greatest net benefit to society.
- Which criterion is it based on, Pareto optimality og kaldor hicks. Normally kaldor hicks

Limitaiton:

Valuation Challenges:
Non-Market Values: Difficult to quantify many environmental benefits in monetary terms, leading to potential undervaluation.
Discounting Future Benefits: Can undervalue long-term environmental benefits and future generations’ well-being.

Distributional Effects:
Equity Concerns: May ignore distributional impacts, disproportionately affecting marginalized communities.
Intergenerational Equity: Focus on current costs and benefits may neglect future generations’ interests.

Moral and Ethical Values:
Intrinsic Value of Nature: May not capture the intrinsic value of nature beyond economic considerations.
Ethical Imperatives: Some policies driven by ethical imperatives (e.g., protecting endangered species) may be undervalued by CBA.

30
Q

What can be reasons for or against including distributional
weights in Cost-Benefit Analysis?

A

Including distributional weights in Cost-Benefit Analysis can enhance the equity and social justice of policy decisions by giving more importance to benefits for disadvantaged groups. However, it also introduces complexity, subjectivity, and potential biases into the analysis.

Reasons For Including Distributional Weights
Equity and Fairness:

Addressing Inequality: Distributional weights can help account for the differing impacts of a project or policy on various income groups, ensuring that the benefits to poorer or more vulnerable groups are given more importance.
Social Justice: Including distributional weights aligns with principles of social justice, ensuring that disadvantaged groups receive greater consideration in policy decisions.
Reflecting Social Preferences:

Public Preferences for Equity: Societal preferences often favor policies that reduce inequality and support vulnerable populations. Distributional weights can reflect these preferences in CBA.
Political Acceptability: Policies that are perceived as fair and equitable are more likely to gain public and political support.
Maximizing Social Welfare:

Diminishing Marginal Utility of Income: Economic theory suggests that the marginal utility of income decreases as income increases. Therefore, benefits to lower-income individuals may contribute more to overall social welfare than equivalent benefits to higher-income individuals.
Holistic Assessment: Including distributional weights provides a more comprehensive assessment of a policy’s impact on overall social welfare.
Reasons Against Including Distributional Weights
Complexity and Subjectivity:

Increased Complexity: Incorporating distributional weights adds complexity to the CBA process, making it more challenging to perform and interpret.
Subjective Judgments: Determining the appropriate weights involves subjective judgments about the value of benefits to different groups, which can be contentious and difficult to standardize.
Focus on Efficiency:

Economic Efficiency: Traditional CBA focuses on economic efficiency, aiming to maximize net benefits without considering distributional impacts. Introducing distributional weights shifts the focus from pure efficiency to equity, potentially complicating decision-making.
Policy Trade-Offs: Some argue that equity concerns should be addressed through other policy mechanisms (e.g., taxation, social welfare programs) rather than through CBA, to keep the analysis of specific projects or policies focused on efficiency.
Data and Measurement Challenges:

Data Limitations: Reliable data on the distributional impacts of policies can be difficult to obtain, making it challenging to apply distributional weights accurately.
Measurement Issues: Quantifying the precise impacts on different income groups and assigning appropriate weights involves complex measurement issues and potential inaccuracies.
Potential for Bias:

Bias in Weighting: The selection of distributional weights could introduce bias, reflecting the values and priorities of the analysts rather than an objective assessment.
Manipulation Risk: There is a risk that distributional weights could be manipulated to favor particular outcomes, undermining the objectivity and credibility of the CBA process.

Conclusion

Policymakers need to carefully consider these factors and balance the goal of economic efficiency with the pursuit of social equity when deciding whether to include distributional weights in CBA.

31
Q

Based on the normative principles of environmental cost-
benefit analysis, what objections could you think of?

Same question in another way

Environmental economists usually assume that the objective of pollution tax policy is to
achieve economic efficiency in resource allocation. Discuss briefly some other objectives that might
also be legitimate and relevant targets for policies against pollution.

A

Objections to environmental CBA:
One may critique the notion that
consumers always know what is best for themselves, implying that they
can be relied on to make rational choices between conventional and
environmental goods

In particular, the following arguments are quite common:
* Individuals may lack adequate information on the consequences for
themselves of the alternatives they face
* Individuals may not think carefully enough about the consequences
of alternative choices
* Individuals may lack self-knowledge, meaning that they cannot
relate the consequences of alternative choices to their preferences
* Individuals’ preferences may not reflect their true interests due to
”preference shaping” arising for socialization processes and
advertising

  • Behavioral economics have dealt with some of these issues
  • Environmental economics recognize issues of imperfect information
    and limited rationality
  • These issues are recognized when asking people to value non-
    environmental goods
32
Q

Where would you categorize a polar bear and the
Amazon rainforest?

A

Polar Bears
Use Values

Actual Direct Use Value:

Tourism and Recreation: Benefits from ecotourism, where people travel to see polar bears in their natural habitat, contributing to local economies.
Actual Indirect Use Value:

Cultural and Educational Content: Benefits from polar bears being featured in documentaries, educational programs, and media, raising awareness and providing educational value.
Environmental Services: Polar bears contribute to the health of the Arctic ecosystem, which has indirect benefits, such as regulating the population of prey species.
Potential Use Value:

Scientific Research: Future utility in studying polar bears for understanding climate change, Arctic ecosystems, and conservation strategies.
Future Ecotourism: Preserving polar bears ensures the potential for future tourism opportunities and economic benefits.
Non-Use Values

Existence Value:

Intrinsic Value: Utility derived from knowing that polar bears exist, reflecting an intrinsic value and a sense of global biodiversity.
Bequest Value:

Intergenerational Altruism: Utility from the possibility of preserving polar bears for future generations to experience and benefit from, reflecting a commitment to conservation and sustainability.
Amazon Rainforest
Use Values

Actual Direct Use Value:

Biodiversity: Direct use of the vast array of species for food, medicine, and raw materials.
Timber and Non-Timber Forest Products: Benefits from harvesting timber, fruits, nuts, and other forest products that support local and global economies.
Actual Indirect Use Value:

Climate Regulation: Benefits from the Amazon rainforest acting as a carbon sink, helping to mitigate global climate change.
Water Cycle and Weather Patterns: Regulation of regional and global water cycles, which benefits agriculture and human settlements.
Cultural and Educational Content: The rainforest’s role in documentaries, educational programs, and books, providing cultural enrichment and learning opportunities.
Potential Use Value:

Pharmaceuticals: Potential future discoveries of medicinal plants and compounds that could lead to new treatments and medical advancements.
Future Resource Use: Ensuring future sustainable use of its resources for timber, food, and other products.
Future Ecotourism: Potential for future ecotourism opportunities, contributing to economic growth and environmental awareness.
Non-Use Values

Existence Value:

Intrinsic Value: Utility derived from knowing that the Amazon rainforest exists, reflecting its intrinsic value and the importance of its biodiversity.
Bequest Value:

Intergenerational Altruism: Utility from the possibility of leaving the Amazon rainforest intact for future generations, ensuring they can benefit from its biodiversity and ecosystem services.

33
Q

What are some of the limitations of the travel costs

A

The idea with revealed preference methods is to reveal people’s true
WTP through the behavior in related markets

Revealed preference methods therefore reveal a lower bound of the
total value
* Let’s focus on two approaches: travel costs and hedonic pricing. Here only travel costs

Introduction

The Travel Cost Method (TCM) is a revealed preference method used in environmental economics to estimate the economic value of non-market goods, particularly recreational sites such as parks, lakes, and wildlife reserves. The method infers the value of these sites by observing the travel expenses incurred by visitors.

Concept and Application

The basic premise of TCM is that the costs incurred by individuals traveling to a recreational site reflect their willingness to pay for access to that site. These costs serve as a proxy for the price of accessing the site, allowing economists to estimate its recreational value.

Key Components

Travel Costs:

Transportation Costs: Expenses related to fuel, public transportation, vehicle maintenance, and other travel-related expenditures.
Time Costs: The value of time spent traveling to and from the site, often calculated based on a fraction of the individual’s wage rate.
Entry Fees: Direct costs associated with accessing the site, such as entrance fees or parking charges.
Data Collection:

Visitor Surveys: Collecting data on the number of visits, origin of visitors, travel expenses, duration of the visit, and socio-economic characteristics of visitors.
Site Characteristics: Information about the recreational site, such as amenities, environmental quality, and accessibility.
Modeling Visitor Demand:

Demand Function: Estimating a demand function that relates the number of visits to the site with the travel costs incurred. This often involves regression analysis to understand how travel costs influence visitation rates.
Consumer Surplus: Calculating the consumer surplus, which represents the total benefit visitors receive from the site over and above what they pay to access it. This is derived from the area under the demand curve above the travel cost line.

Strengths of the Travel Cost Method

Revealed Preferences: TCM is based on actual behavior rather than hypothetical scenarios, providing more reliable estimates of value.
Policy Relevance: Useful for informing policy decisions related to the funding, maintenance, and preservation of recreational sites.
Non-Market Valuation: Provides a way to value non-market environmental goods that are not traded in traditional markets.

Limitations of the Travel Cost Method (TCM) in Simpler Terms
Uniform Utility Assumption:

Complex Models: In some models, it’s assumed that all visitors get the same enjoyment from environmental features, which may not be true. (This can be adjusted in more advanced models).
Overstated Travel Costs:

Multiple Trip Purposes: If visitors have other reasons for their trip besides visiting the site, their travel costs might be higher than the actual cost of just visiting the site.
Variable Time Value:

Work Hour Constraints: If people can’t freely choose their working hours, the value of their time can vary, complicating the calculation of travel costs.
Assuming Known Choices:

Choice Set Assumption: These models often assume we know all the possible places visitors could choose to visit, which might not always be accurate.
Objective vs. Subjective Measures:

Measuring Environmental Quality: There can be problems if we only measure environmental features objectively rather than considering how visitors personally perceive them. (Hedonic Pricing can sometimes address this issue by looking at how property prices reflect environmental attributes).

Example Application

Consider a national park that attracts visitors for its scenic beauty and recreational opportunities. Using TCM, researchers can:

Survey visitors to collect data on travel expenses, time spent traveling, entry fees paid, and socio-economic information.
Estimate the demand function by analyzing how variations in travel costs impact the number of visits.
Calculate the consumer surplus, providing an estimate of the park’s recreational value to inform policy and management decisions.

34
Q

Environmental economists usually assume that the objective of pollution tax policy is to
achieve economic efficiency in resource allocation. Discuss briefly some other objectives that might
also be legitimate and relevant targets for policies against pollution.

A

Again, there is no single “objectively correct” answer to this question, but
the textbook by Perman et al. (2011) mentions the following alternative targets for pollution policy:

a) Sustainability and ecological goals. For ethical reasons, voters and policy makers may want to
set targets for pollution that would avoid a decline in biodiversity and/or preserve certain unique
ecosystems. This could be seen as especially important if environmental damage to the ecosystems
is deemed to be irreversible beyond certain “tipping points”. If there is uncertainty about these
tipping points, the Precautionary Principle of environmental policy may call for a tighter pollution
target than the one suggested by a standard cost-benefit analysis like the one underlying the
10
pollution tax rule (ix). However, even if the pollution target is set on the basis of sustainability and
ecological goals, the environmental economist could still provide useful advice on cost-effective
ways to meet the target, say, via environmental taxes or tradeable pollution permits.

b) Human health protection. In the areas of air pollution and water pollution, the pollution targets
are often set with the purpose of protecting public health by keeping the concentration of pollutants
at levels that do not imply “unacceptable” risks to public health. These targets are rarely identified
through systematic cost-benefit analysis, although they may to some extent be influenced by the
costs of reducing pollution. This approach to the setting of pollution standards reflects the notion
that one particular cost of pollution – i.e., its damaging impact on human health – is particularly
important and should therefore be decisive for standard setting.

c) Public preferences. Points a) and c) are examples of how particular public preferences (possibly
expressed through voting processes) may legitimately affect pollution policy. Another such example
could be the public’s notion of distributional fairness which could lead to pollution targets that
reflect a concern for the distributional impact of environmental policy. For example, some NGOs
and policy makers might favour environmental policies that tend to redistribute income from rich to
poor and might be sceptical of the use of environmental taxes or other environmental policy
instruments if these are deemed to be regressive. However, as discussed in the answer to Question
5, environmental policy may not be an efficient way of achieving income redistribution when the
government has access to other policy instruments such as a progressive income and/or targeted
public transfers to disadvantaged groups in society.

35
Q

Now suppose that the economy actually consists of many heterogeneous consumers
with different earnings capabilities resulting in an unequal distribution of income. Suppose further
that the government cannot impose individualized non-distortionary lump sum taxes to correct for
undesirable inequalities in income distribution but that it can impose a progressive income tax.
Discuss whether a government in such a society would want to stick to the rule for the optimal
pollution tax that you derived in Question 4. (Hint: You are not asked to do any formal
mathematical analysis here; a verbal discussion suffices).

A

There is no single “objectively correct” answer to this question, so an answer
that reflects coherent economic reasoning and makes intuitive sense is satisfactory.

A natural starting point for the discussion is that the pollution tax rule (ix) in Question (4) is a pure
efficiency rule that does not incorporate any concern about income distribution (which is natural
since the underlying model assumes that all consumers are identical). When consumers differ in
their earnings capacity so that the income distribution is unequal, a utilitarian government will be
concerned about the resulting unequal distribution of welfare. However, one could argue that the
government should use the progressive income tax to achieve the desired distribution of income and
raise the necessary revenue and then stick to the efficiency rule (ix) to secure an efficient reduction
of pollution. This is a sensible answer to the question.
An advanced answer may point out that the progressive income tax will distort labour supply and
that the pollution tax will exacerbate this distortion by further eroding the disposable real wage.
Hence it might be that the government would want to keep the pollution tax rate somewhat below
the Pigouvian level prescribed by (ix) in order not to exacerbate the pre-existing income tax
distortion to labour supply too much even if this implies a higher level of pollution than the first-
best Pigouvian level. This would also be a thoughtful satisfactory answer to the question.

Finally, if for some reason the government cannot freely design the income tax schedule so as to
attain all the income redistribution it would prefer, the government may want to consider the
distributional effects as well as the environmental effect when choosing the level of the pollution
tax rate. Specifically, if the pollution tax is estimated to be regressive, say, because expenditures on
the dirty good (which could be fossil fuel) make up a relatively larger share of the budgets of poorer
families, the government might want to keep the pollution tax rate below the Pigouvian level for
distributional reasons (and vice versa if the pollution tax is deemed to be progressive). This would
also be an acceptable answer to the question

36
Q

Problem 1
* [No preparation needed.] While some economists argue for the creation of private property rights to protect the environment, many of those concerned for the environment find this approach abhorrent (= causing or deserving strong dislike or hatred). What are the essential issues in this dispute?

A

Pros:

The establishment of private property rights, where none previously existed, is likely to improve both static and dynamic allocative efficiency of environmental resources.

Owners of the resources can account for the opportunity costs of access, extraction, or harvesting. These costs can be built into the prices paid by resource users. This scenario is more likely to result in a resource use path over time that corresponds to a social optimum than in the absence of property rights.

It may also lead resource allocation closer to a sustainable pattern, although an efficient outcome is not necessarily a sustainable one.

Cons:

However, it is not difficult to find ethical objections to the creation of private property rights.

- In more affluent economies, many individuals argue—largely from ethical premises—that mountain or wilderness areas should be held collectively by a broadly defined community. They believe that future generations have inalienable rights to these resources as well. 

In many parts of the world, there are long-established collective or common rights to water, grazing lands, harvestable species, and the like. It is easy to see potential conflicts between maintaining cultural traditions and the goal of economic efficiency.

Not induvidual based property rights, but groups maybe:

Having said this, there is no reason why private property rights need to be individually based. All that is required is that a well-defined set of persons is endowed with property rights, and that this set is sufficiently small so those rights can be enforced at reasonable cost.

Example: Water Rights in Australia

Scenario: Water Allocation in the Murray-Darling Basin
- Before Property Rights: Water use in the Murray-Darling Basin was largely unregulated, leading to over-extraction and severe environmental degradation.
- After Property Rights: The Australian government established water entitlements and trading schemes, allowing water rights to be bought and sold.
- Static and Dynamic Allocative Efficiency: Farmers and industries consider the cost of water in their production decisions, leading to more efficient use and conservation efforts.
- Sustainability: Water trading encourages the transfer of water to higher-value uses and promotes conservation.
Ethical Considerations:
- Opposition: Critics argue that water trading can lead to water being concentrated among wealthier users, disadvantaging small farmers and communities.
- Cultural Impact: Indigenous communities may view water as a communal resource with spiritual significance, conflicting with commodification.