Admin Law - Legitimate Expectation Articles Flashcards
Justification behind the law - criticism: lack of coherence - list
- Uncertainty on role of detrimental reliance.
- Uncertainty on the role of expectation.
- Uncertainty of macropolitical area with less intensive review.
- Double deference.
- Mistaken representations not binding.
- Not giving consideration to promise makes it more likely to be binding.
Justification behind the law - criticism: lack of coherence - uncertainty on role of detrimental reliance
> Justification for it not being required does not seem convincing.
-Schiemann LJ in Bibi: reliance can be without change of position since the lack of action can be in reliance, furthermore the weakest in society will be penalised since they have less choices, detriment is in the form of moral detriment due to disappointment at result; but then the applicant has not lost anything as a result of his expectation.
-Lord Kerr in Finucane: detrimental reliance is not required since consistency of treatment is required by the standards of good administration.
Justification behind the law - criticism: lack of coherence - uncertainty on the role of expectation
> In some cases it was held that a clear and unambiguous representation is required and the representation must be understood: Begbie & Bancoult.
-But in Bancoult there was a 3-2 split on whether the statement was clear and unambiguous.
But in other cases it was held that an existing practice/policy would also suffice (Coughlan).
-Clayton: this is unsatisfactory as it is not appropriate to use the principle of LE, the principle of consistency is more suited.
Then in Mandalia it was held that expectation is not required: new wider principle of consistency: this gave the area of law more clarity, but it is uncertain what are its requirements including the standard of review.
Justification behind the law - criticism: lack of coherence - uncertainty of macropolitical area with less intensive review
> In Coughlan, the provision of assisted living facilities was held not to be in the field of policy & a substantive outcome was ordered, but in Bibi housing of homeless was held to be in the field of policy and only a procedural remedy was ordered.
In BAPIO policy relating to the training of doctors was not held to be in the field of policy and a substantive outcome was ordered, but in Begbie a decision on the funding of students was held to be in the field of policy and no remedy was ordered.
Justification behind the law - criticism: lack of coherence - double deference
> In both substantive review & determining the outcome in SLE cases.
Justification behind the law - criticism: lack of coherence - Mistaken representations not binding
> In some cases it was held that these cannot give rise to LE: Begbie & Nadarajah.
It suggests that the rationale is good administration (of preventing intentional departures), rather than fairness, the applicant is required to bear the burden of the mistake.
But shouldn’t the principle of good administration also deter mistakes?
Justification behind the law - criticism: lack of coherence - not giving consideration to promise makes it more likely to be binding: Bibi
> Suggests that the focus is more on the procedure of the decision rather than the substantive outcome in an SLE case.
Goes against the rationale of fairness, more of ensuring good administration.
Craig & Schonberg, ‘Substantive Legitimate Expectations after Coughlan’ [2001] PL 684 - intro
> The general approach in Coughlan was correct but the standard of review could be further refined in order to render it more precise.
1. Case Law prior to Coughlan
2. Coughlan: principled justification
3. Refining the Approach in Coughlan
4. Effect of HRA
5. Conclusion
Craig & Schonberg, ‘Substantive Legitimate Expectations after Coughlan’ [2001] PL 684 - case law prior to Coughlan - 3 Qs
> There was controversy as to 3 Qs:
1. Is there a free-standing principle of substantive LE in English administrative law at all?
2. In what specific circumstances may an individual be said to hold a reasonable or LE?
3. Is the standard Wednesbury reasonableness, or should the courts apply a more exacting standard of review?
Craig & Schonberg, ‘Substantive Legitimate Expectations after Coughlan’ [2001] PL 684 - first question - list
> Is there a free-standing principle of substantive legitimate expectations in English administrative law at all?
- First category of cases.
- General policy has been departed from in a particular case.
- General policy replaced by another policy.
- Another line of authority which casts the existence of SLE into doubt.
Craig & Schonberg, ‘Substantive Legitimate Expectations after Coughlan’ [2001] PL 684 - first question - first category of cases
> The judgments in Preston, MFK and Unilever are clearly authority for the existence of a principle of SLE in relation to representations or course of conduct.
Even though they are couched in terms of abuse of power and substantive fairness than LE.
It is unclear what would be the test for review if PA were to argue that there was public interest rationale.
Craig & Schonberg, ‘Substantive Legitimate Expectations after Coughlan’ [2001] PL 684 - first question - general policy has been departed from in a particular case
> Khan:
-Alleged departure from policy on adoption of family members from abroad, Denning LJ required a hearing to be granted & overriding public interest before going back on LE.
> Ruddock: telephone call case.
-The test for review is unclear: in Urmaza it was stated to not be bare rationality but disproved in Gangadeen.
Craig & Schonberg, ‘Substantive Legitimate Expectations after Coughlan’ [2001] PL 684 - first question - general policy replaced by another policy
> In Hamble Fisheries Sedley J came out strong in favour of SLE in such cases.
The test is not bare rationality but fairness (whether LE is more important than policy choice).
Craig & Schonberg, ‘Substantive Legitimate Expectations after Coughlan’ [2001] PL 684 - first question - another line of authority which casts the existence of SLE into doubt
> Hargreaves
- Rejected Hamble Fisheries as wrong in principle & the court could only interfere if the administration’s decision was irrational.
Craig & Schonberg, ‘Substantive Legitimate Expectations after Coughlan’ [2001] PL 684 - Coughlan: principled justification - list
> The issue of principle.
Groundwork laid by 4 propositions
Principled justification for the approach in Coughlan
Craig & Schonberg, ‘Substantive Legitimate Expectations after Coughlan’ [2001] PL 684 - Coughlan: principled justification - issue of principle
> Mark Elliot contends that the Wednesbury test provides the proper standard of review in terms of constitutional principle.
Craig & Schonberg, ‘Substantive Legitimate Expectations after Coughlan’ [2001] PL 684 - Coughlan: principled justification - groundwork laid by 4 propositions
> Separation of powers based on relative competencies of different branches, to sanction general judicial intervention simply because the court would prefer a different choice would lead to a reallocation of power.
Courts feel less reticent about considering the propriety of purpose & irrelevancy:
-Rationale is that the courts are merely demarcating the 4 corners of power ascribed to the decision maker by the legislature.
-Courts will often have a choice as to whether to characterise the issue raised by a case as going to, for example, relevancy rather than rationality.
While there should not be substitution of judgment there should be control in terms of rationality.
The very fact that the intensity with which the Wednesbury test is applied varies in cases of fundamental rights, is a recognition that the standard of rationality review should be defined in accordance with the nature of the interest in question.
Craig & Schonberg, ‘Substantive Legitimate Expectations after Coughlan’ [2001] PL 684 - Coughlan: principled justification - principled justification for the approach in Coughlan
> We have already seen that the courts will take account of the nature of the applicant’s interest when fashioning the appropriate standard of review.
-It is generally acknowledged that cases where individual rights are affected by the exercise of administrative discretion are at the top of the hierarchy of interests which the law should protect. Cases involving a proven substantive legitimate expectation should properly be next on the list.
-Such an expectation, while falling short of a right stricto sensu, nonetheless carries a moral force or weight which should not be ignored when determining the appropriate standard of review.
- First, by acting contrary to what it has led an individual to expect, a public body may cause that individual severe hardship.
-Compensation based on tort or statutory compensation schemes are not a satisfactory alternative to substantive protection of expectations.
-How would a lost chance of adoption from abroad be compensated. - Secondly, protection of LEs is closely linked with the RoL.
-Thus, to protect LEs by principles of administrative law is a way of giving expression to the requirements of predictability inherent in the RoL. - Thirdly, a lack of respect for LEs may undermine trust in public authorities.
-Trust is highly valuable because individuals are more likely to participate in decision-making processes, to co-operate with initiatives, and to comply with regulations devised by authorities which are perceived as trustworthy. - Finally, public authorities must comply with the general principles of EU law, including that of LE, in situations which fall within the scope of Community law.
- The EU law principle of LE requires the English courtrs to go beyond review of bare rationality or Wednesbury unreasonableness.
-If the test of review in purely domestic situations is bare rationality, the courts and the administration will have to apply different public law principles to what may in practice be very similar fact patterns.
Craig & Schonberg, ‘Substantive Legitimate Expectations after Coughlan’ [2001] PL 684 - Refining the approach in Coughlan
> The approach was correct to go beyond bare rationality.
-That undervalues the nature of the applicant’s interest, and would provide scant protection for the individual.
Abuse of power does not in and of itself, provide a criterion for deciding whether the reasons advanced by the PA are sufficient.
> Proposed approaches:
- Reason by analogy from the more intense application of the Wednesbury test used in cases concerned with rights: heightened scrutiny but relaxed.
-Expectations are not normatively equal to HRs. They should therefore not be subject to exactly the same standard of review. - Formulation of the Wednesbury test suggested by Lord Cooke in ITF: whether the decision was one which a reasonable authority could reach.
-However, it does not provide a standard of JR for cases of the kind under consideration here. - Proportionality
- More precise, structured test of review than the notion of abuse of power applied in Coughlan.
- Consideration of necessity. - Weighing, or balancing, the requirements of substantive fairness against any overriding interest relied upon for taking an action which would disappoint the expectation:
- This balancing approach is somewhat lacking in precision.
- Unclear what the extent of imbalance should be.
- It is submitted that the courts should interfere with the administration only if there is a significant imbalance between the public & private interests at stake.
- Less structured type of analysis than proportionality, but it is clearly a more precise standard of review than the notion of abuse of power in and of itself.
-Strikes an appropriate balance between administrative autonomy & judicial control.
Craig & Schonberg, ‘Substantive Legitimate Expectations after Coughlan’ [2001] PL 684 - Effect of HRA
> When the article was written HRA had just come into effect.
Conjectures:
-Cases might concern both LE & HRA.
-The HRA may therefore lead to a drop in the number of applications for JR being based on LE arguments.
-If a case raises both a claim under the HRA and an independent claim based on LEs then they should be decided separately, according to the standard of review appropriate to each.
- This was the way in which the court approached the matter in Couhglan where it dealt with breach of promise and the right to a home separately.