1.5 - problem of evil Flashcards
Epicurus (problem of evil)
(342-270BCE)
- is God willing but not able to prevent evil? (then he is not omnipotent)
- is God able to prevent evil but unwilling? (then he is not omnibenevolent)
- is He both able and willing? (then why do we suffer)
David Hume (problem of evil)
(1779)
1. God is not omnipotent
(or)
2. God is not omnibenevolent
(or)
3. Evil does not exist
Hume concluded that God must be impotent or malicious as it was evident that evil exists.
J. L. Mackie (problem of evil)
(1955)
The conjunction of any two of the inconsistent triad, entails the negation of the third. The triad is:
point A = omnipotence
B = omnibenevolence
C = evil exists.
possible problems with Mackie’s inconsistent triad
- there could be a loving reason for evil (free will)
- could reject that evil exists (an attempt made by Augustine, evil is a necessary part of the world)
- is God omnibenevolent? - the God in the Old Testament doesn’t always seem loving, He stokes genocides, fails to forgive, and encourages acts of cruelty
- Process Theology (God is not able to control evil)
‘it can be shown, not that religious beliefs lack…’
‘it can be shown, not that religious beliefs lack rational support, but that they are positively irrational, that the several parts of the essential theological doctrine are inconsistent with one another…’ - J. L. Mackie
two possible responses to Mackie’s inconsistent triad
- to deny the existence of evil
- Hume believed there is too much evidence for the existence of evil in the world (not an a-priori argument)
- Augustine attempted to change the nature of evil from a substance to a privation (a lack of something - good)
- however it still seems counter-intuitive to deny evil - God may have a good reason for allowing evil to exist (Plantinga’s response)
Plantinga’s response to the inconsistent triad/problem of evil
God may have a good reason for allowing evil to exist - 1932
Plantinga argues that it is NOT formally contradictory to say
1. God is omnipotent
2. God is omnibenevolent
3. God is omniscient
4. Evil exists
> with the hidden assumption: God creates a world containing evil and has a good reason for doing so
- this not a proof for the existence of God but it is a logical rebuttal of Mackie’s position
- there does not need to be a God for Plantinga’s defence to work
- for the argument to work, we do not even need to know what the good reason is, only that there might be one
Plantinga’s free will defence
A possible good reason for the allowance of evil is that God wishes to create beings to be significantly free. It would be impossible for: God to create a good world with free will, without the possibility of evil existing. There would be no real choice if there was no risk of harm.
In terms of natural evil, it gives the opportunity for free will.
If Plantinga’s free will defence is true then it is possible that the proposition: God creates a world containing evil and has a good reason for doing so is true. Hence the provision of free will to creatures could supply a good reason for God creating a world containing evil.
William L. Rowe’s stance
- agrees with Plantinga that evil does not disprove the existence of God
- there could be examples of evil which God allows because of some greater possible good
- BUT not all evil is like this…We can imagine evils which God could stop without losing a greater good or permitting a greater evil
- Rowe believes that if evidence of such evils are found they will be unnecessary and unjustifiable. Is it reasonable to believe that all seemingly pointless instances of animal and human suffering may not be avoided by an Omni-God? To which Rowe answers no.
Rowe’s argument
- there (probably) exists instances of suffering which an omnipotent, omniscient being could have prevented without thereby losing some greater good or permitting some evil equally bad or worse.
- An omniscient, wholly good being would prevent the occurrence of any intense suffering it could, unless it could not do so without losing some greater good or permitting some evil equally bad or worse
- There (probably) does not exist an omnipotent, omniscient, wholly good being.
What example does Rowe give to defend his proposition: ‘there (probably) exists instances of suffering which an omnipotent, omniscient being could have prevented without thereby losing some greater good or permitting some evil equally bad or worse.’
the fawn in the forest (a serious case of natural evil):
- lightning strikes a dead tree resulting in a fire which causes injury and suffering for the fawn, after several dies death relieves the suffering
- ‘So far as we can see, the fawn’s death is pointless’
- Rowe acknowledges that this doesn’t prove the first premise because the fawn’s suffering COULD have a purpose however he asks whether we can reasonably believe that all seemingly pointless instances of animal and human suffering may be unavoidable for an omni-God
‘In some distant forest…’
‘In some distant forest lightning strikes a dead tree, resulting in a forest fire. In the fire, a fawn is trapped, horribly burned, and lies in terrible agony for several days before death relieves its suffering’ - Rowe
- Rowe’s defence of his first proposition
‘So far as we can see, the fawn’s suffering…’
‘So far as we can see, the fawn’s suffering is pointless. For there does not appear to be any greater good such that the prevention of the fawn’s suffering would require either the loss of that good or the occurrence of an evil equally bad or worse’ - Rowe
how does Plantinga challenge Rowe?
- We cannot dispute that instances of evil occur. However Rowe’s claim that the fawn’s suffering is ‘apparently pointless’, and does not justify the existence of God, is a stretch too far and might be branded as an ‘inductive leap’ (black swans).
- ‘Perhaps God has a good reason, but that reason is too complicated for us to understand, or perhaps he has not revealed it to us for some other reason.’ - Plantinga
- Eg. you cannot move from ‘I cannot see the fly my cat is chasing’ to ‘There is no fly my cat is chasing’ - cats can see small, fast moving objects better than we can.
- this position is unfalsifiable, so it stops the debate - is this an easy way out?
Book of Job
(Judaism but recognised in all Abrahamic faiths):
- even if we can’t understand what the possible reasons are behind an act of suffering, there could be one - God understands the complexity of the world to minute detail we will never and could never understand
- Epistemic distance - the separation in knowledge and understanding between us and God
epistemic distance
the separation in knowledge and understanding between us and God
problem of divine hiddenness
(response to book of job)
- analogy of a loving parent - sometimes parents do things that cause us some pain, for our benefit (we just don’t understand) eg. horrible tasting medicine when we are sick
- however the parent is there to reassure and comfort, but God doesn’t behave this way. When we need comfort during our suffering, God is not there.
HOWEVER, if we rely on the idea of an afterlife, it could be argued that he is not an absent parent as he will be there to explain to us.
Vardy’s king and peasant girl analogy
(support’s Plantinga’s argument)
A king is out for the ride, and sees a peasant girl who he falls madly in love with at first sight. He has two options:
1. he could ride up to her there and then, and she would feel obligated to follow him
2. or he could come back and try to woo her as the average peasant
Similarly, God gives us the chance to love him and have faith without feeling like we have to (he preserves our freedom). It’s about forming a relationship through trust.
‘God dies the death of…’
‘God dies the death of a thousand qualifications’ - Flew
- if we can’t agree or test it in a sensible way, it becomes an empty idea - we may as well not have one
Augustine’s life
- he had a divided home with his father hostile to Christianity and his mother a devout christian
- his father was said to be unfaithful to his mother
- when studying in school he began a life ‘lustful relationships’ resulting in a 13-year ‘arrangment’ with a lower-class woman which resulted in a son
- his first engagement with philosophy was with ‘Mancheanism’ which may have appealed given the conflicts he saw between his parents
- He then sent his mistress away as she was ‘an obstacle to a suitable marriage’ but took up another after a couple of years.
- When engaged to be married, he came across ‘Neo-Platonist’ ideas - this developed the idea of a corrupted physical body and evil as a lack of good
- When Augustine was deciding whether to convert to Catholicism and be baptised or not, he had a religious experience
‘Manicheanism’
(one of the schools Augustine engaged with - the first one)
- a sort of Christian inspired cult which viewed the world as a cosmic struggle between the forces of good and evil. They believed people had two souls, one good and one evil, which pull the individual in different directions and create constant internal struggle (REMINISCENT OF PLATO). The human soul is naturally part of the kingdom of light but becomes trapped in the kingdom of darkness due to the appetites of the body. It makes sense that this would appeal to Augustine due to the constant conflict between his parents
- follows of Manicheanism believed that evil had always existed so was just as real and eternal as God
‘Neo-platonist’
(One of the schools Augustine engaged with - the second one)
this developed the idea of a corrupted physical body and expressed a shame of living in the body (this could explain any shame he felt around his relationships). For Plotinus there is only one Form of goodness, “Not Evil”. This unlocked the idea that evil is not a substance at all but rather a privation or lack of good
Augustine’s religious experience
- When Augustine was deciding whether to convert to Catholicism and be baptised or not, he heard ‘take it up and read’ being recited and opened the Bible. The first passage he read went as such:
‘Not in revelling in drunkenness, not in lust and wantonness, not in quarrels and rivalries. Rather arm yourself with the Lord Jesus Christ. Spend no more thought on nature and Nature’s appetites.’ - Romans