the problem of evil Flashcards
the problem of evil
- uses the existence of evil in the world to argue that God (as defined in the concept of God) does not exist
- these arguments can be divided into two forms:
1. the logical problem of evil - deductive argument that says the existence of God is logically impossible given the existence of evil in the world
2. the evidential problem of evil - an inductive argument which says that, while it is logically possible that God exists, the amount of evil and unfair ways it is distributed in our world is pretty strong evidence that God doesn’t exist
evil
- evil is any kind of suffering
- moral evil - evil that comes from human choices
- natural evil - evil that comes from a natural source
what is god like
- omnipotent - all powerful
- omnibenevolent - all good
- omniscient - all knowing
- omnipresent - exists everywhere
- many philosophers think that an omnipotent being would have to be omniscient and omnipresent, so sometimes these do not get mentioned as it is assumed they are covered by omnipotence
deduction and induction
arguments can be divided into two kinds:
- deductive: an argument where the conclusion follows logically from the premises - if the premises are true, then the conclusion must be true
- inductive: an argument where the conclusion is evidentially supported by the premises - if the premises are true, then the conclusion is very likely to be true
the logical problem of evil
- if god were all powerful, he would have the ability to stop evil
- if god were all loving, he would want to stop evil
- if god had the ability to stop evil and wanted to stop evil, then evil would not exist
- evil exists
- therefore, god is not all powerful, or not all loving, or both
- the logical problem of evil claims that it is impossible for god to exist, and for there to be any amount of evil in the world
the evidential problem of evil
- there exist instances of intense suffering which an omnipotent, omniscient being could have prevented without thereby losing some greater good, or permitting some evil equally bad or worse
- an omniscient, wholly good being would prevent the occurrence of any intense suffering it could, unless it could not do so without thereby losing some greater good or permitting some evil equally bad or worse
- (therefore) there does not exist an omnipotent, omniscient, wholly good being (Rowe 1979:336)
the factual premise
- premise 1 is a statement of fact: there exists gratuitous evil
- gratuitous evil is any evil where there is no reason that would justify permitting that evil to exist
- Rowe’s example: ‘in some distant forest lightning strikes a dead tree, resulting in a forest fire. in the fire a fawn is trapped, horribly burned, and lies in terrible agony for several days before death relieves its suffering’
- Rowe claims that it is very likely that something like this has happened, and that no good has come from it
- so, it is very likely gratuitous evil exists
the theological premise
- premise 2 above is the theological premise: a statement about what religion claims about god
- it is less controversial than premise 1
- it claims that god would prevent any suffering that was not achieving some greater good
- one exception is William Hasker: he argues against premise 2 - if god did not allow gratuitous evil, we would have no reason to try to stop evil
theodicy
- theodicy - a justification of god in the face of the presence of evil
- a response to the logical problem only requires showing that it is possible for god and evil to both exist
- a response to the evidential problem requires showing that the existence of evil does not make it likely that god does not exist
response to the logical problem of evil - good could not exist without evil
- without evil, good couldn’t exist
- Mackie’s response: imagine if we lived in a world where everything was red, presumably, we wouldn’t have created a word for ‘red’, nor would we know what it meant if someone tried to explain it to us. But it would still be the case that everything is red, we just wouldn’t know - God could have created a world in which there was no evil. Like the red example, we wouldn’t have the concept of evil. But it would still be the case that everything is good – we just wouldn’t be aware of it
response to the logical problem of evil - the world is better with some evil than none at all
- some evil is necessary for certain types of good
- e.g., you could not be courageous (good) without having to overcome fear of pain, death, etc. (evil)
- we can define first and second order goods: first order good (e.g., pleasure), second order good (e.g., courage)
- second order goods seek to maximise first order goods
- and second order goods are more valuable than first order goods
- but without first order evils, second order goods couldn’t exist
- Mackie’s response: if we accept that first order evil is necessary for second order good to exist, how is second evil order explained; second order evils seek to maximise first order evils such as pain, so, for example, malevolence or cruelty are examples of second order evils. But we could still have a world in which people were courageous (second order good) in overcoming pain (first order evil) without these second order evils
- so why would an omnipotent and omnibenevolent God allow the existence of second order evils if there is no greater good in doing so?
response to the logical problem of evil - we need evil for free will
- we can develop the second order evil argument above further and argue that second order evil is necessary for free will
- and free will is inherently such a good and valuable thing that it outweighs the bad that results from people abusing free will to do evil things
- so, while allowing free will brings some suffering, the net good of having free will is greater than if we didn’t
- therefore, it’s logically possible that an omnipotent and omnibenevolent God would allow evil (both first order and second order) for the greater good of free will
- Mackie’s response: an omnipotent God can create any logically possible world, if it’s logically possible to freely choose to act in a way that’s good on one occasion, then it’s logically possible to freely choose to act in a way that’s good on every occasion
- so, an omnipotent God could create a world in which everyone freely chooses to act in a way that’s good, there is a logically possible world with both free will and without second order evils
- this, surely, would be the best of both worlds and maximise good most effectively: you would have second order goods, plus the good of free will, but without second order evils, this is a logically possible world – the logically possible world with the most good
- so, why wouldn’t an omnipotent and omniscient God create this specific world? Second order evils do not seem logically necessary, and yet they exist
evil in an ancient world
- for many ancient philosophers, the existence of evil was explained by some fundamental evil in the world
- e.g., Plato thought the matter was inherently evil (chaotic and disordered), and that the forms were good (they brought order to the physical world)
- for monotheists, this cannot be correct as that would mean that god would have created evil
Augustine
- Augustine claimed that god created everything and that he made all things good
- why is evil even possible
- Augustine claimed that if something good exists, then evil is always possible because evil is a privation of good
- evil is the absence of something good, e.g., sickness is the absence of a well functioning body
- Augustine thought this explained why evil was possible, but not why it actually exists
free will
- Augustine thought that human free will explains the existence of evil
- god gave humans free will and humans have used that to bring about evil
- therefore, god is not responsible
- two key claims:
1. god cannot stop us freely choosing evil
2. free will is a significant moral good