TEST #3 Flashcards
principle of charity
we must interpret the author’s argument in a fair way
we must make the argument as strong as possible without twisting their word and staying consistent with what the speaker had in mind
when reconstructing an argument, make sure:
1) the premises are reasonable for the author
2) the argument is well-formed for the author
3) the argument is undefeated (in cogency cases)
principle of charitable interpretation
has to do with implicit premises
when adding implicit premises, add ones that are reasonable to believe rather than ones that are obviously false, and ones that are consistent with what the author had in mind
deductive strength
- argument is valid
- reasonable to believe all the premises are true, based on available evidence (doesn’t say anything about the truth-value)
it is unreasonable to disbelieve the conclusion.
recall principle of proportional belief
if the premises of a valid argument are known to be true, then the conclusion is also known to be true
the premises can fail to be reasonable to be true by the available evidence making it r/j/r to believe the claim is false or to suspend judgment.
falibilism still exists! an arg. can be deductively strong but the conclusion is false
inductive strength
- argument is cogent
- all premises are reasonable to believe, based on evidence
- argument is not defeated by persons total evidence
it is unreasonable to disbelieve the conclusion of an inductively strong argument
DEFEATED ARGUMENT: when some other evidence provides good reason to believe the conclusion is false or should suspend judgment about it
- if the current premises mixed with the additional premises/information doesn’t support the conclusion
conclusion indicators
therefore
thus
hence
entails
implies
… follows that
premise indicators
deductive/inductive weakness
when an argument doesn’t meet one or all the requirements for strength
e.g. can be valid but not reasonable
e.g. can be reasonable but not cogent
strength for one person but not for another
depends on the evidence available to each person. certain evidence makes it reasonable for one person to believe the premises to be reasonable, whereas other evidence makes the premises unreasonable to believe for another person.
strength at one time but not another
a person may gain/lose evidence overtime; at one time the evidence makes it reasonable to believe the premises, at another it does not
strength and proprotional belief
proportion the strength of your belief of the premises to be true to the evidence available:
the stronger the evidence for the premises, the mroe reasonable it is to believe them
if it is r/j/r to believe the premises of a valid argument are true, then it is r/j/r to believe that the conclusion is true as well
r/j/r comes in degrees. so the more r/j/r it is to believe the premises of a valid argument are true, the more reasonable it is to believe the conclusion is true as well
(if theres a lot of evidence that premises of a valid argument are true, then you should believe with great strength that the conclusion is true too)
sound arguments vs strong arguments
SOUND ARGUMENTS: valid arguments with true premises (independent of rational thought)
STRONG ARGUMENTS: valid arguments that depend on how reasonable it is to believe the conclusion
circular arguments
arguments with the same premise and conclusion
valid but weak since they’re unjustified
ways in which a valid/cogent argument can fail to be strong for you
the available evidence gives reason to suspend judgement or disbelieve the truth of the premises
reminder
in valid arguments, the premises provide CONCLUSIVE evidence for the conclusion (if the premises are reasonable, then so is the conclusion)
cogent arguments do not have conclusive evidence (the premises always leave some room for the conclusion to be false)
can a deductively strong argument be defeated?
no because the premises guarantee the truth of the conclusion 100%,s o noa dditional evidence can sway that