Revision: Homo Economicus Flashcards
Name the three conditions for rationality.
Completeness, continuity, and transitivity.
What type of preferences does transitivity rule out? Provide a basic example.
Rules out “cyclical” preferences. Such as: A > B, B > C, and C > A.
Suppose person X holds A and has cyclical preferences A > B, B > C, and C > A. Describe how X would spend money to increase their utility and name the fallacy.
X would spend a sum of money to trade A for B, the more to trade B for C, then more to trade C for A ad infinitum until broke. This is called the money pump.
Describe continuity in terms of a bundle of different goods containing X and Y.
There exists another bundle of goods, containing one unit fewer of X and some more of Y, that is preferred to the original bundle.
Is continuity an accurate assumption about real-life decision-making?
Not really. Consider a basket of goods with “health” and “safety”. It’s unlikely you’d find anyone willing to give up any amount of health for more safety, even though the axiom suggests rational agents would accept some trade-off.
The argument holds even less weight, when considering examples such as “health” and “apples”.
Describe how a “lexicographic order” can lead to discontinuous preferences observed in real life that go against continuity.
An example of a lexicographic order is Olympic medals. Overall Olympic ranking is based, first, on how many gold medals each country has won then, in the case of a tie, on the number of silvers, and finally the number of bronzes.
This suggests there is no number of silver medals ever as good as one gold - a direct contradiction to continuity.
Describe the axiom of completeness and what answer to a set of choices is supposedly rules out.
For any pair of options, A and B, either A preferred to B, B preferred to A, or the two are regarded as equally good. This rules out the “I don’t know” answer when a rational agent is presented with a choice.
Is completeness a reliable axiom in real life?
No, incomplete information is a common problem in daily decision-making and is the crux of the “lemon and plum” thought experiment.
Describe the basics of “utility maximisation”.
A rational agent will apply a numerical value to all options in a choice set. This value is known as utility, and a decision-maker that chooses the option with highest utility is known as a utility maximiser.
How does utility maximisation tie into the three axioms of rationality; completeness, continuity, and transitivity?
Anyone whose preferences are consistent with completeness, continuity, and transitivity will behave as a utility maximiser.
Utility-maximising problems with complete information seldom exist in reality; instead, utility maximisation under uncertainty is more common. What is the decision to make under these conditions?
Choose the option in the given choice set with highest expected utility.
Describe how a “risk averse” individual would choose between two options that lead to the same average outcome but with different uncertainty.
A risk averse individual would always choose the less uncertain of the two choices. They would choose a guaranteed £5 payout over a 50:50 bet to gain either £0 or £10 despite the expected payout of each being £5.
Imagine a utility maximiser is presented with either a guaranteed £5 or 50:50 bet between £0 and £10. They choose the guaranteed £5. What does this suggest about their preferences and utility profile?
The individual is risk averse and enjoys greater utility from a guaranteed £5 that a bet of equal expected value. A diminishing marginal utility to income .
The St. Petersburg paradox poses an indefinite series of coin tosses. You start with a pot of £1; if heads, the pot doubles and you play again; if tails, you walk away with the pot. Describe how the expected value of this gamble contradicts utility maximisation under uncertainty.
The expected utility of this gamble is technically infinite, as summing all the expected payouts of an indefinite series is infinity! However, you would be hard pressed to find an individual to bet their life’s savings on the first toss, despite it technically being worth it.
What economic concept acts as a solution to the St. Petersburg paradox - the infinite series betting game?
Decreasing marginal utility of income. Assume each win of the infinite game awards a fixed unit of income despite the pot doubling. As the game progresses, the utility derived from an additional victory is not worth the monetary risk.