Religious Language ; C20 perspectives and philosophical comparisons Flashcards

1
Q

Logical Positivism

A

In the 1920s, a group of philosophers developed a form of scientific reasoning known as logical positivism.The logical positivists were concerned with the relationship between the use of language and knowledge, rejecting as meaningless what they saw as non-cognitive (fact-free) claims.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
2
Q

Vienna Circle

A

meetings regularly took place in Vienna and as such, the group became commonly known as the Vienna Circle.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
3
Q

Influence of Ludwig Wittgenstein

A

VC/LP were influenced by Ludwig Wittgenstein.
Early in his career, Wittgenstein suggested that meaningful language is connected with the things we know from our senses.The logical positivists caught on to this idea and used it to challenge religion: how could religious language link with sense experience?

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
4
Q

A.J Ayer on the word ‘God’

A

The term ‘God’ is a metaphysical term ( outside of human sense proportion) And if ‘god’ is a metaphysical term, then it cannot even be probable that God exists. For to say that ‘God exists’ is to make a metaphysical utterance which cannot be either true or false. And by the same criterion, no sentence which purports to describe the nature of a transcendent god can possess any literal significance.’

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
5
Q

Ayer on the existence of God

A

Ayer does not just deny God’s existence; he denies the possibility of God’s existence altogether on the grounds that there is no way of empirically verifying his existence.
Because of this, Ayer would disagree with all the traditional arguments for the existence of God as none of them conclusively and empirically prove the existence of God.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
6
Q

The Verification Principle

A

Verification means checking a statement to see if it’s true. The verification principle simply states that: “a statement which cannot be conclusively verified … is simply devoid of meaning.”

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
7
Q

Analytic propositions

A

Verificationists like Ayer believe that statements can only be meaningful if they can be demonstrated, and these can be divided into two types:
Analytic propositions, which are true by definition, either because:
This is required by the definition of the words used – e.g. ‘this circle is not a square.
They are mathematical – e.g. ‘2+2=4’.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
8
Q

Synthetic propositions

A

Synthetic propositions are true by confirmation of the senses.
E.g. ‘I can see that it’s roast for lunch on a Thursday’.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
9
Q

Ayer’s view of religious claims

A

Ayer thought that religious claims are non-cognitive and impossible to verify, so they are meaningless.
He does not say that they are just false; it is more that they cannot really tell us anything at all.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
10
Q

Flaw of verification: requires conclusive proof

A

But for many logical positivists, even A.J. Ayer himself, the principle is problematic. As it requires conclusive proof through observation or experience, it suggests that obviously meaningful statements are meaningless.
For example, statements that we make such as ‘dinosaurs lived on the earth’ can’t be verified through observation or experience, so we cannot accept the statements as meaningful.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
11
Q

Modifications to the verification principle

A

a weaker version of the verification principle was brought into play. This weaker verification makes two modifications.
Statements that attempt to say something about the world are meaningful if it is possible in principle to gather the evidence i.e. do we know how such statements could be verified?
Conclusive proof is not always possible. So statements that attempt to say something about the world are factually meaningful if experience and observation can establish statements as probable.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
12
Q

Wittgenstein’s view of conception

A

Wittgenstein advocated that we should not talk about what we cannot understand, famously saying: “whereof one cannot speak, thereof one must remain silent.”
In short, while we may not be able to sense or conceptualise some things, they may still have truth or reality. But to conjecture ( an opinion or conclusion formed on the basis of incomplete information) on such points is ultimately meaningless.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
13
Q

Meaning depends on the scenario

A

Wittgenstein suggested that the meaning of words is determined by the language game that the words are part of (so the meaning of a word would depend on the scenario it was used in).
For Wittgenstein, words perform a function in a language; they do not signify an object.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
14
Q

Wittgenstein’s chess analogy

A

For Wittgenstein, the use of language was like partaking in a game. To use a word, you have to first understand how it works.
Wittgenstein’s classic example was the game of chess. You might be told that a piece is called a ‘king’, but without understanding the rules of chess, you could never use the piece.
He also stated that to argue about how language is used is meaningless. If you want to play the game, you must accept the rules. You cannot play chess if your opponent is trying to play checkers.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
15
Q

Rules of language

A

Wittgenstein suggested that language, and therefore the rules of that language, can be seen from two sides:
Those who are inside the game and therefore know the rules.
Those who are outside the game and therefore do not know the rules.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
16
Q

Language games

A

Wittgenstein’s main point is that the meaning of a statement is not to be understood by the steps you would take to verify or falsify it, but by the context ( forms of life)in which it is used.
Wittgenstein believes that there are different contexts in which language is used. These he calls language games.
Religion is one and science, for example, is another.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
17
Q

The Falsification Symposium: Flew’s Argument

A

After he encountered difficulties with the verification principle, Anthony Flew developed the idea that a statement could be verifiable if the empirical evidence that would prove it was false was known .Statements are meaningful because they can be shown to be false.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
18
Q

White swan example

A

He applied this idea to religious language.The statement ‘all swans are white’ is often used to show how a proposition can be false. We may see hundreds of white swans but this does not prove the statement. However, when we see one black swan, we know that the proposition is false.Statements such as ‘all swans are white’ are meaningful because they can be shown to be false. This statement is synthetic and empirically testable.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
19
Q

Flew on religious beliefs

A

Flew argued that religious people tend to refuse the possibility of their statement being false and so make their statements meaningless.
They will not allow evidence to discredit their beliefs and so their statements are meaningless.
Flew is protesting about a tendency he observed amongst religious believers to shift the goalposts of statements about God.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
20
Q

‘God loves all humans’ example

A

For example, someone might start by saying that ‘God loves all humans’.
If that person were to witness a child dying of inoperable cancer of the throat, they would be right to use that as evidence that the claim ‘God loves all humans’ is false.
Flew observed that religious believers would then retort ‘…but God loves humans in an inscrutable way, a different way to the way we love.’
In Flew’s opinion, this second statement has no meaning because it doesn’t allow for anything to falsify it.

21
Q

The Parable of the Invisible Gardener

A

originally told by John Wisdom. It was later developed by Antony Flew, The idea/essence of the story is as follows: Imagine two explorers come across a clearing in a forest in the clearing there are both pretty flowers and also weeds growing. One explorer says to the other, “There must be a gardener because there are flowers growing.” The second explorer doesn’t believe this because a good gardener would remove the weeds from the area. But he is willing to test this, so they set a number of traps, Each time a new trap is installed the gardener is not seen. So is there a gardener? Well the first explorer’s answer is that the gardener is first evasive, the explorer then takes more qualities away from the gardener and says that the gardener is now silent, then invisible, and undetectable. The main point of the parable is that the second explorer then replies, “What’s the difference between that (an invisible gardener) and no gardener at all?” This is of course an analogy which is meant to be compared to God, and how some people say that God can’t be detected and so perhaps they are just guessing rather than knowing with any evidence that God exists.

22
Q

The Falsification Symposium: Hare’s Argument

A

The philosopher RM Hare came up with a response to falsification. This was called the theory of ‘bliks’. Hare used a parable to illustrate his point.

23
Q

Parable of the lunatic

A

‘A certain lunatic is convinced that all dons want to murder him. His friends introduce him to all the mildest and most respectable dons that they can find, and after each of them has retired, they say, “You see, he doesn’t really want to murder you; he spoke to you in a most cordial manner; surely you are convinced now?” But the lunatic replies “Yes, but that was only his diabolical cunning; he’s really plotting against me the whole time, like the rest of them; I know it I tell you.” However, many kindly dons are produced, the reaction is the same.’

24
Q

Explanation of the ‘blik’

A

The paranoid student cannot imagine being wrong; his statement ‘all dons want to murder him’ is unfalsifiable.
And yet, Hare argues that this belief remains very meaningful.
So a ‘blik’ is a particular view about the world that may not be based upon reason or fact and that cannot be verified or falsified; it just is and we don’t need to explain why we hold our ‘blik’.

25
'Blik' car example
Hare talked about trusting in the metal of a car. This ‘blik’ about the car meant that we would quite happily drive or be driven in a car because we have the ‘blik’ that the metal is strong and that it is safe to drive at high speed in the car. Hare said that people either have the right or sane ‘blik’ or the wrong or insane ‘blik’; the 'lunatic' in Hare's quotation has the wrong ‘blik’ about dons, whereas his friends have the right ‘blik’.
26
Hare's conclusions
So Hare argues that it is possible to agree to a proposition which is not falsifiable but is nonetheless meaningful. According to Hare, we all have fundamental beliefs or principles on which we base our actions and which we will never give up.
27
Falsification Symposium: Mitchell's Theory
Mitchell disagreed with the theory of ‘bliks’ and suggested another way of using religious language, using another parable.
28
Belief & language based on fact
Mitchell claimed that religious belief, and therefore religious language, is based upon fact, although they are not straightforwardly verifiable or falsifiable. He used the idea of a resistance fighter to make his point.
29
Resistance movement example
'A member of the resistance movement is met one day by a man claiming to be the leader of the resistance movement. The fighter is suitably impressed and pledges his loyalty to the stranger. As time goes on, the fighter sees the ‘leader’ helping out the resistance, but at other times he is apparently helping out the enemy. The fighter nevertheless carries on in his belief that the stranger is, in fact, the leader of the resistance movement'.
30
Difference: Mitchell & Hare
Hare’s 'lunatic' has a) no reason for mistrusting dons and b) won't allow anything to count against his belief. Mitchell’s fighter, however, is a) willing to admit that things count against his belief in the leader (a symbol of God) and b) grounds his belief in reason and fact: he trusts this man who claims to be the leader and has examples of him fighting for the resistance.
31
Mitchell's criticism of Flew
Mitchell claimed that Flew missed the point that believers have a prior commitment to trust in God based on faith. For this reason, they do not allow evidence to undermine their faith.
32
Mitchell's conclusions
Mitchell’s point is that religious belief is based upon facts, but that belief cannot be verified/falsified in the simplistic way that the logical positivists demand. Of course, the stranger in the story will be able to reveal his true allegiance after the war and explain his mysterious behaviour, in the same way that all the peculiar and problematic parts of religious belief will be revealed at the end of time according to traditional religious belief.
33
Locke and Hume's support
John Locke and David Hume's arguments support the verification principle. As empiricists, they argue that truth and knowledge should be known via our senses. This form of reasoning goes back to the early Greek Philosopher Aristotle who based his beliefs on scientific evidence.
34
Weak verification
A.J Ayer's theory of weak verification states that to be meaningful, a statement does not have to be verifiable but instead must be shown to be true within reasonable doubt. Weak verification means we can make statements about history, scientific theories and human emotion but not religion and ethics. For example, if we know in principle how to verify a statement, then it is meaningful. If the probability weighs in favour of the statement, then it is meaningful.
35
verification theory is not meaningful
But one of the most significant criticisms is that the statement of the theory itself does not pass the test as a meaningful statement. The verification theory cannot be verified by sense experience and so is not a meaningful synthetic proposition.
36
Problems with analytic proposition
What's more, if the statement is analytic, then it is giving a new sense to the word ‘meaningful’; a new definition which we do not necessarily have to accept. The idea that all meaningful synthetic statements have to be empirically verifiable also causes practical problems. Many of the claims in science, such as the existence of black holes, cannot be verified by sense experience.
37
History cannot be tested
Many historical statements about past events cannot now be tested using the senses. Theologian and Philosopher Vincent Brummer argues that to treat sentences of faith as if they were scientific sentences is to commit an error of understanding. Brummer, like D.Z. Phillips before him believes that scholars such as Hume and Dawkins are wrong to assume that if something is not scientific or measurable then it is somehow not significant. We should not say that the entire contents of reality can possibly be known to science.
38
Popper's view of vertification
The philosopher Karl Popper was the inspiration behind the falsification principle and he pointed out that if meaning depended upon strong or weak verification, then the whole of science would be wiped out. This is because none of the general laws of science are actually verifiable. We can never accept any statement as verifiable. Instead, we can only accept a statement up to the point where it is falsified. Therefore, the verification principle is not successful.
39
Tillich's symbol argument
Tillich argued God is not ‘a being’ but ‘being itself’ and that religious language is not cognitive (it can't be known) but symbolic. Symbols are not the same as facts. So it is wrong to criticise them as if they were. Symbols cannot be verified or falsified. This doesn't mean symbols are meaningless, even if they are unverifiable; they can be effective or ineffective ways of drawing religious believers to ‘the power of being’.
40
'Bliks' can be meaningful
In the same way, a ‘blik’ could be intensely meaningful to a person who has one.
41
Criticisms: falsification principle
could argue that Flew’s confidence in empirical evidence as the final test of meaning is, in itself, unfalsifiable.
42
Response to Flew's question
Flew’s article finishes with the question, ‘what would have to occur or to have occurred to constitute for you a disproof of the love of, or the existence of God?’ The religious believer might want to respond to him with a similar question, ‘what would have to occur or to have occurred, to constitute for you a disproof of the primacy of empirical evidence
43
Swinburne's view of assertions
Richard Swinburne argues that we do not have to be able to specify what would count against an assertion for that assertion to be meaningful. He argues that we cannot specify what would count against scientific theories of the beginnings of the universe, for example, because we do not know enough about the scientific theories involved, but this does not make the scientific theories meaningless to us.
44
Wittgenstein: life commitment
Ludwig Wittgenstein argued that religious language isn’t just the asserting of facts, but a commitment to a way of life. So it would seem that Wittgenstein's non-cognitive approach makes more sense than a cognitive approach. This is because much of the language used to describe the nature of God is metaphysical and beyond our realm of understanding.
45
Aquinas: factual statements
In Aquinas' view, religious language puts forward factual statements about supernatural reality. This fits with most believers' understanding of what they are doing when they say God exists – they are asserting a fact. For example, when a religious person claims that God is omnipotent, they are aiming to say factually that God is all-powerful.
46
Comparing Wittgenstein and Aquinas' Theories
Aquinas and Wittgenstein agree on God's unknowable nature and that religious language has to be understood in particular ways. They disagree about religious language as fact.
47
d.z. phillips analyses language games cognitively
he says religion and philosophy are different games both have different meanings of ‘god’ so they cannot be the same but there are religious philosophers, so surely you can be part of both groups? as a reductionist, phillips aims to reduce everything down to the simplest possible explanation he argues ‘god exists’ are is expressions of belief “Talk about God’s reality cannot be considered as talk about the existence of an object”
48
don cupitt argues a non-cognitive approach is needed
he says a misunderstanding occurs whenever we interpret religious language in ‘realist‘ terms talk of God is really just talk of human experiences to speak of ‘God’ is to subscribe to a certain set of values and a certain way of seeing the world he says we should understand theological language in this non-realist way