religious language Flashcards

1
Q

cognitive

A

aim to literally describe how the world is
are true or false
triangles have three sides

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
2
Q

non cognitive

A

do not aim to literally describe how the world is
are not true or false
dont do that

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
3
Q

verificationism

A

only statements that can be verified are meaningful

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
4
Q

falsificationism

A

only statements that can be falsified are meaningful

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
5
Q

AJ AYERS verification principle

A

a statement only has meaning if it is either:

An analytic truth (e.g. “a triangle has 3 sides”)
Empirically verifiable (e.g. “water boils at 100c”)
Any statement that does not fit these descriptions is meaningless, according to verificationism. This is a similar claim to Hume’s Fork from epistemology.

Applying the verification principle to religious language, Ayer argues that statements like “God answers my prayers” and “God exists” are not analytic truths. Further, they are not empirically verifiable or falsifiable (see below).

Therefore, according to Ayer’s verificationism, religious language is meaningless.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
6
Q

problem with verification

A

Ayer’s claim that “a statement is only meaningful if it is analytic or empirically verifiable” is itself neither an analytic truth or empirically verifiable! Therefore, according to its own criteria, the verification principle is meaningless.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
7
Q

falsifiability

A

Despite how it may sound, falsifiability is not about being true or false. Instead, falsifiability is part of what it takes for a statement to be meaningful.

Falsifiable statements are meaningful and capable of being true or false
Unfalsifiable statements are meaningless, and not capable of being true or false.

A statement is falsifiable if it is inconsistent with some possible observation. In other words, there has to be some possible evidence that could count against that statement – otherwise the statement is meaningless.

The statement “water boils at 100°c” is falsifiable because it could be proven wrong by some possible observation. For example, if we heated a beaker of water and it didn’t boil despite a reliable thermometer showing 500°c, this observation would count against the statement. So, “water boils at 100°c” is a falsifiable and meaningful statement because there are possible tests that could prove it wrong.

In contrast, the statement “everything in the universe doubles in size every 10 seconds” is unfalsifiable because no possible observation could disprove it. You could use a ruler to measure things every 10 seconds but this couldn’t disprove the claim because you could just say that the ruler doubled in size as well! There is seemingly no possible experiment that could disprove the statement “everything in the universe doubles in size every 10 seconds” and so it is unfalsifiable and meaningless.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
8
Q

anthony flew invisible gardener

A

Anthony Flew gives the following analogy in an attempt to show that religious language – in particular the statement “God exists” – is unfalsifiable, and therefore meaningless:

Two explorers find a clearing in a jungle. Both weeds and flowers grow here.
Explorer A says the clearing is the work of a gardener. Explorer B disagrees.
To settle the argument, they keep watch for the gardener.
After a few days, they haven’t seen him, but Explorer A says it’s because the gardener is invisible
So, they set up an electric fence and guard dogs to catch the gardener instead
But, after a few more days, they still haven’t detected him
Explorer A then says that not only is the gardener invisible, he’s also intangible, makes no sound, has no smell, etc.
Explorer B: What is the difference between this claim and the claim that the gardener doesn’t even exist?
In other words, Explorer A’s theory is unfalsifiable – nothing could possibly prove this theory wrong, but nothing could prove it correct either.
Because it is unfalsifiable, Explorer A’s theory is meaningless.
In case it’s not obvious:

Jungle clearing = the world
Invisible gardener = God
Flowers = Good
Weeds = Evil
So, Flew is arguing that “God exists” is meaningless because it is unfalsifiable in the same way the existence of the invisible gardener is unfalsifiable. We can’t even use the problem of evil as evidence against God’s existence because the religious believer just creates reasons (e.g. free will, soul-making) why an omnipotent and omnibenevolent God would allow evil.

Flew argues that because the religious believer accepts no observations count as evidence against belief in God, the religious believer’s hypothesis is unfalsifiable and meaningless.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
9
Q

hicks eschatological verification

A

Eschatological verification: A statement that can be verified after death, or at the end of time.

John Hick agrees with Ayer that “God exists” is not empirically verifiable in this life. However, Hick argues that many religious claims are about things beyond the limits of human life. And, he argues, such religious claims are falsifiable because it is possible to verify them after we die. For example, many theists believe in a life after death during which they will meet or otherwise experience God (which would be unambiguous verification that “God exists” is true).

To illustrate this, Hick tells a parable of a ‘celestial city’:

Two men are travelling on a road – it is the only road there is, so they both must travel it
Traveller A believes the road leads to a celestial city, whereas Traveller B believes the road leads nowhere and that the journey is meaningless
As they travel along the road, they experience both “refreshment and delight” and “hardship and danger”
When they turn the last corner of the road, one of them will be proved right: If traveller A is correct and there is a celestial city, his belief will be verified.

In this parable, Traveller A is the theist and Traveller B is the atheist. The “hardship and danger” represents the problem of evil. If the theist is correct, his belief will be verified in the afterlife when he meets God – this is the equivalent of reaching the celestial city.

So, in response to Ayer’s verification principle, Hick says “God exists” is verifiable (and therefore meaningful). It may not be empirically verifiable, but it is eschatologically verifiable: If “God exists” is true, then it can be verified after we die.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
10
Q

basil mitchells resistance fighter

A

Mitchell agrees with Flew that in order for a statement or belief to be meaningful it must be possible for some observation to count against it (i.e. it must be falsifiable in order to be meaningful).

But, Mitchell argues, just because there are some observations that count against a certain belief, that doesn’t automatically mean we have to reject that belief. Mitchell gives the following example to illustrate this:

You are in a war, your country has been occupied by an enemy
You meet a stranger who claims to be leader of the resistance
You trust this man
But the stranger acts ambiguously, sometimes doing things that appear to support the enemy rather than your own side
Yet you continue to believe the stranger is on your side despite this and trust that he has good reasons for these ambiguous actions
In this analogy, the stranger represents God and his ambiguous actions represent the problem of evil. Mitchell is arguing that we can accept that the existence of evil counts as evidence against the statement “God exists” (and so it is falsifiable) without having to withdraw from belief in this statement.

Mitchell argues that religious beliefs are not ‘provisional hypotheses’ like scientific statements that the believer is totally detached from. But nor are religious beliefs ‘vacuous formulae’ that the believer holds regardless of any evidence to the contrary.

Instead, reasonable religious beliefs are a kind of middle ground: They are ‘significant articles of faith’. The religious believer is invested in these beliefs and so doesn’t withdraw from them as soon as the slightest evidence to the contrary turns up. However, this is not to say that the religious believer would believe “God exists” in spite of overwhelming evidence to the contrary – that would be irrational or, to use Mitchell’s term above, a ‘vacuous formulae’.
So, Mitchell is arguing that we can accept that the existence of evil counts as evidence against God’s existence (and so “God exists” is falsifiable and meaningful) without withdrawing belief in God.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
11
Q

rm hare and bliks

A

According to Hare, religious statements are not things that can just be shown to be true or false. Instead, they are basic fundamental beliefs that are not empirically testable – Hare calls these attitudes ‘bliks’.

To illustrate what bliks are, Hare uses the example of a paranoid student who thinks university lecturers are trying to kill him.

You assure this student that university lecturers are not trying to kill him and provide tons of evidence, yet the student still believes it anyway. Imagine, for example, that you decide to go with him to speak to a university lecturer and the lecturer acts totally normal:

You: See, he’s fine – the university lecturer isn’t trying to kill you!

Paranoid student: But he was just pretending to be normal so as not to reveal his true plan to kill me!

So, no amount of evidence/reassurance will convince the student that his blik is false. In other words, their blik is unfalsifiable.

But despite being unfalsifiable, Hare argues that bliks are still meaningful to the person who holds them. In the case of the university lecturers example, the blik clearly means something to the paranoid person because it has an effect on his behaviour: He won’t go to lectures, and will look over his shoulder to check university lecturers aren’t following him, for example.

Hare argues that religious language is the same: “God exists” may be unfalsifiable to people who have this blik, but it clearly means something to them. For example, people who believe “God exists” might pray or go to Church – it means enough to them that it affects their behaviour.

In other words, a blik is unfalsifiable but still meaningful to the person who holds it.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly