Quiz 1 Flashcards

1
Q

Q1: According to Moore, an account of “good” ought to be the first task of an ethical analysis because…

A

…it is the fundamental object which defines the scope and realm of ethics. Any mention of the term “good” invokes ethical matters.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
2
Q

Q1: Moore’s Goal

A

Present the fundamental principle of ethics, then provide a detailed investigation of how they can be applied in particular circumstances

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
3
Q

Q1: Moore’s Strategy

A

“Clear the conceptual ground” to define the theory of value

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
4
Q

Q1: Moore’s Objective

A

Conceptual analysis of the term “good”

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
5
Q

Q1: Moore’s Tactic

A

Analytic Philosophy (philosophy of analyzing concepts)

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
6
Q

Q1: What is the question of Moore’s primary concern?

A

How is “good to be defined”?

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
7
Q

Q1: Why can’t “good conduct” be the first task of an ethical analysis?

A

Good Conduct cannot be the first task of an ethical analysis because it does not start at the foundation of ethics…

  • Describing ethical SUBJECTS is a complex notion (not all conduct is good and some is bad)
  • Things other than conduct may be considered good
  • Examining good conduct alone could result in a mistaken attribution to good that is not shared
  • Could limit enquiry to conduct alone
  • Can be biased/influenced by author’s opinion
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
8
Q

Q1: An account of good avoids…

A

giving personal advice or exhortation

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
9
Q

Q1: Why can’t “good things” be the first task of an ethical analysis?

A

“Good” is a true definitional statement; true by definition.Therefore, it is a FALLACY to equate properties evident in “good Xs” with the definition of good.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
10
Q

Q1: What is Moore’s thesis about an ethical analysis of the term “good”?

A

It is a rational error to try to define good by reference to any other natural or metaphysical concept.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
11
Q

Q!: Why does Moore conclude that good is a simple term.

A

Good is a simple term because we cannot list its essential separate components (like horse) because it is a simple/atomic idea that has no more basic components (like yellow).

Good is indefinable in the most important sense.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
12
Q

Q1: Why can’t “good conduct” or “good things” be the first task of an ethical analysis?

A

There is a difference between “good” and “the good” and Moore is focused with the former while good conduct and good things focus on the latter.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
13
Q

Q2: Naturalistic Fallacy

A

It is a rational error/mistake in reason to try to define good by reference to any other natural or metaphysical concept.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
14
Q

Q2: Explain the Naturalistic Fallacy

A

You cannot define a term that is in the category of the non-natural (e.g. good) by reference to the category of the natural (e.g. yellow). Any ethical theory which grounds its view on an understanding that good depends on natural properties is supported by a flawed conceptual foundation.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
15
Q

Q2: How does Moore support the Naturalistic Fallacy?

A

The Open-Question Argument

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
16
Q

Q2: Open-Question Argument

A

P1: If “good” is not a simple term, there are only two alternatives: it is complex or it is meaningless.
P2: “Good” is not a complex term.
P3: “Good” is not a meaningless term.
C: Good is a simple and independently meaningful term, therefore it cannot be defined by reference to any other concept (whether it is simple, complex, natural, metaphysical).

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
17
Q

Q2: What is the conclusion of the Open-Question Argument?

A

It is a mistake of reason to maintain that “good” is anything other than a simple term because it is always independently meaningful, which by extension implies that it is fallacious to define “good” by reference to any other concept (whether it is simple, complex, natural, metaphysical)

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
18
Q

Q2: How does Moore explain P2: “Good” is not a complex term?

A

Moore shows that “good” is not a complex term by considering it as such…
Complex definition of good: Y is good if it is desirable to desire Y (i.e. good is desiring the objectively desirable)

However, we can always ask if it is good to desire Y; Is it good to desire good in that way?

It is therefore an open Q as to whether the object of the definition and the definition itself is good.

The openness of the Q shows that “good” remains a concept that is independent of any purported conceptual components

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
19
Q

Q2: (P2) The openness of the Q shows that

A

“good” remains a concept that is independent of any purported conceptual components

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
20
Q

Q2: How does Moore explain P3: “Good” is not a meaningless term?

A

Moore shows that “good” is not meaningless in the same way…
In any attempt to equate good with some other concept (good is pleasure), we can always still ask, is pleasure good?
Pleasure is PLEASANT, but is pleasure GOOD?

Good = Y … but is Y good?

When equating the term “good” with another term, it is always an open Q as to whether a concept equated with good is, itself, good.

The openness of the Q shows that “good” is meaningful.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
21
Q

Q2: (p3) The openness of the Q shows that

A

When equating the term “good” with another term, it is always an open Q as to whether a concept equated with good is, itself, good. Therefore, “good” is meaningful.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
22
Q

Q2: Why does the openness of the Qs shows that “good” is neither complex, nor meaningless?

A

The openness of the Qs shows that “good” is neither complex, nor meaningless, because we can always still inquire about its properties and meaning.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
23
Q

Q2: How does the Open Question Argument support the Naturalistic Fallacy?

A

Moore shows it is fallacious to define good by reference to ANY other concept since “good” is independently meaningful. Good cannot be equated with or compared to any other concepts. The openness of the Qs means we can always further challenge the comparison/equation.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
24
Q

Q3: Frankena writes a narrow critique of Moore because

A

too many are accusing others of committing the Naturalistic Fallacy, while no one has actually identified what the fallacy is and everyone has ignored what is actually at issue.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
25
Q

Q3: Frankena’s thesis

A

The NF is neither a logical error, nor a quasi-logical error, rather the “fallaciousness: is what is at issue between the INTUITIONISTS (non-naturalists; Moore) and the DEFINISTS (naturalists; Bentham, Mill).

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
26
Q

Q3: The Definist Fallacy…

How does Frankena explain that the error of Moore’s NF has been misunderstood?

A

The problem (of the NF) is not crossing the line between categories (defining non-natural terms by reference to natural terms). The problem is taking one of the members of a set of innumerable concepts as COMPLEX. Complex terms can be defined by reference to other terms, Simple terms are not synonymous.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
27
Q

Q3: Why does Moore call it the NF? Why is he wrong to call it this, according to Frankena?

A

Moore calls it the NF because he thinks it manifests itself in crossing categories, however, Frankena points out that it is actually a DEFINITIONAL problem.
It does not violate Hume’s rule (you cannot get an ought from an is), but instead makes a more GENERIC/BASIC error…

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
28
Q

Q3: How is the Definist Fallacy more basic than the Naturalistic Fallacy?

A

It does not violate Hume’s rule (you cannot get an ought from an is), but instead makes a more GENERIC/BASIC error…

The problem is simply that…
Two properties are being treated as one, and it is irrelevant if one of them is natural/non-ethical or non-natural/ethical

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
29
Q

Q3: The Definist Fallacy

A

The process of confusing two properties, defining one property by another, or substituting one property for another.

The Definist Fallacy holds that terms (ethical or non-ethical, natural or non-natural) must have a unique meaning, then all other definitions are impossible. Therefore, it will ALWAYS be a mistake to use synonyms to articulate the meaning of a term, since those synonyms suggest the meaning of, for example good, is NOT uniquely independent of all other terms (when it actually is).

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
30
Q

Q3: The Definist Fallacy holds that terms (ethical or non-ethical, natural or non-natural)

A

must have a unique meaning, then all other definitions are impossible. Therefore, it will ALWAYS be a mistake to use synonyms to articulate the meaning of a term, since those synonyms suggest the meaning of, for example good, is NOT uniquely independent of all other terms (when it actually is).

31
Q

Q3: What is the primary dispute between the intuitionists and the deifinists?

A

The primary dispute between the intuitionists and the deifinists is their perception of language.

32
Q

Q3: What/Who are naturalists/definists?

A

There is a set of scholars (e.g. Bentham and Mill) who take good and pleasure to be the same thing.

33
Q

Q3: What/Who are non-naturalists/intuitionists?

A

Those who take terms to be independently meaningful, that is, impossible to be defined in reference to other terms/properties.

34
Q

Q3:Why does Moore disagree with the definists?

A

Moore disagrees with the definists because there are two concepts being related to each other that are two independent and unrelated concepts.

35
Q

Q3: What is THE problem according to Frankena?

A

The DEBATE between the definists and the intuitionists, because as soon as they agree on one, the fallacy will be resolved an no longer exists. However, they will never agree with/give in to the other side because they perceive language differently.

36
Q

Q3: Intuitionists believe that

i.e. non-naturalists

A

definists are suffering from “moral blindness,” just like colour blindness

Example: red is different from green, so they should see that pleasure is different from good

37
Q

Q3: Definsits believe that

i.e. naturalists

A

intuitionists are suffering from “hallucinations,” because they are seeing two things when there is just one

Example: pleasure and good are the same thing, but intuitionists see them as two separate things

38
Q

Q3: Overall, what is the object of the debate between the intuitionists and definists?

A

peoples’ different perceptions of language.

39
Q

Q3:Frankena concludes that there will be no resolution because

A

neither side will give into the other since it is difficult to convince others of your own perception.

40
Q

Q4: Thomson’s article is an attack on utilitarianism (and specifically Moore) because

A

the defining elements of utilitarianism are all flawed because they presuppose an independent property of goodness

41
Q

Q4: Thomson’s thesis

A

“all goodness is goodness in a way”

42
Q

Q4: Thomson’s thesis that “all goodness is goodness in a way” means

A

Good changes drastically from context-to-context because every time good is used in different ways, it means something different

43
Q

Q4: What is Moore’s mistake? What is all of Utilitarianism’s mistake?

A

Moore’s mistake: good is an indefinable term that’s meaning is independent of any specific context

Utilitarianism’s mistake: whatever definition you settle on is THE definition and exists/is invoked independent of the context

44
Q

Q4: Thomson does not disagree that good is indefinable, but she does disagree that

A

there is an independent meaningful property of good that is consistent across all text

45
Q

Q4: Why there is an independent meaningful property of good that is consistent across all text?

A

Because good is a modifier and modified

46
Q

Q4: There are _____ and _____ ways of being good

A

external and internal

47
Q

Q4: External uses of the word good are _______ .

A

FUNCTIONAL; they are good for fulfilling some purpose

48
Q

Q4: External uses of good describe the degree to which something is good

A

at
to
for

49
Q

Q4: Examples of EXTERNAL uses of the term good

A

a good sunset (good to look at)
a good swimmer (good at swimming)
a good hammer (good for hammering)

50
Q

Q4: True or False?

Good carries across the specific contexts of good sunset, swimmer, hammer.

A

False.

Good does not carry across the specific contexts. It simply modifies the positivity that is connoted.

51
Q

Q4: How is good a MODIFIER in external uses?

A

Good modifies, in the same way, the positivity implied in each term. (BUT its meaning changes with context.)

52
Q

Q4: When describing something as good (good swimmer) good is

A

PARASITIC on the idea that one just knows the context and knows what it means to be, for example a good swimmer

53
Q

Q4: In internal characteristics of good,

A

good is modified.

54
Q

Q4: Examples of INTERNAL uses of the term good

A

a good person
a good government
good with children
good for stirring

55
Q

Q4: What claim does Moore make that Thomson attacks?

A

Moore: good is a simple property; a context-independent property which communicates the same meaning given any context every single time

56
Q

Q4: Why does Thomson disagree with Moore? On what grounds?

A

According to Thomson, good does not have an independent property because it is both a modifier of and modified by its context.

57
Q

Q4: Is there any part of “goodness” that exists cross-context? How does Thomson conclude?

A

In every use of the term good, good connotes positivity but does not denote anything. There is an implication of “something” positive with every use of “good,” but there is not an independent cross-context meaning. All goodness is goodness in a way.

58
Q

Q5: A.J. Ayer is a

A

radical Logical Empiricist

59
Q

Q5: Ayer’s Aim:

A

to show that ethical concepts do not acquire any factual content and are therefore meaningless

60
Q

Q5: Why do ethical concepts add NO factual content to a proposition?

A

Ethical concepts are unanalyzable because they are “PSEUDO-CONCEPTS” in the sense that they add no factual content to any statement in which they are included

61
Q

Q5: Why are ethical concepts are unanalyzable?

A

They are Pseudo-Concepts

62
Q

Q5: Why are ethical concepts only pseudo-concepts?

A

The addition of an ethical term does not affect the CONTENT of a sentence, therefore purely ethical statements can never be shown to be True or False

63
Q

Q5: If ethical concepts do not have factual content, what are “ethical judgements”?

A

“Ethical Judgements” are purely EMOTIVE, they do not communicate anything to be True or False, rather they just stimulate feeling

Example:
“It was wrong to steal that money” = “You stole that money and that made me upset”

64
Q

Q5: Why are ethical judgements purely emotive? Give an example.

A

they do not communicate anything to be True or False, rather they just stimulate feeling.

Example:
“It was wrong to steal that money” = “You stole that money and that made me upset”

65
Q

Q5: Why is it impossible to identify the propositional content of ethical sentences?

A

SO understood, it is impossible to identify the propositional content of ethical sentences because they do not contain any.

66
Q

Q5: What are ethical judgements used to express? (hint: only speaker’s emotions?)

A

Ethical judgements are not, however, only used to express the speaker’s feelings, but also to provoke feelings in their audience

67
Q

Q5: What does Ayer say about emotions and Necessary Possession? Why?

A

However, Ayer also wants to deny that when you express an emotion, you must NECESSARILY POSSESS the emotion because necessary possession means being IN that psychological state, and THAT can be proven to be True or False.

68
Q

Q5: How does Ayer explain the fact that people appear to engage in legitimate disputes about values?

A

We only appear to be in legitimate disputes about value, but are not in actuality. We do not ever actually argue about values and moral truth because it is not a legitimate object of dispute.

69
Q

Q5: Ayer acknowledges that his argument is subject to Moore;s objection to subjectivism, which states that

A

Subjectivism undermines the possibility of ethical disagreement.

We cannot ever argue about what Right and Wrong is because, according to Subjectivists, the standard of True and False is personal belief.

HOWEVER, it appears we DO argue about moral problems, therefore subjectivism (and potentially Ayer) are false.

70
Q

Q5: What is Ayer’s response to Moore’s objection to subjectivism?

A

We only appear to be in legitimate disputes about value, but are not in actuality. We do not ever actually argue about values and moral truth because it is not a legitimate object of dispute.

We DO argue with facts; we merely argue about our understanding of facts, motives and effects of actions.

BUT, those are EMPIRICAL disputes which deal with facts.

We DO NOT ever argue about actual moral problems or engage in meaningful rational arguments about moral sense, we are simply arguing about how our shared values (e.g. culture, upbringing, etc.) apply to particular sets of facts.

71
Q

Q5: What DO we argue about in ethical disputes?

A

We DO argue with facts; we merely argue about our understanding of facts, motives and effects of actions. BUT, those are EMPIRICAL disputes which deal with facts.

72
Q

Q5: Can we ever engage in meaningful rational arguments about moral sense and moral problems? When we do argue about these, what are we actually arguing about?

A

We DO NOT ever argue about actual moral problems or engage in meaningful rational arguments about moral sense, we are simply arguing about how our shared values (e.g. culture, upbringing, etc.) apply to particular sets of facts.

73
Q

Q5: When we do argue about moral problems, what are we actually arguing about?

A

We are simply arguing about how our shared values (e.g. culture, upbringing, etc.) apply to particular sets of facts.

74
Q

Q5: What important point does Ayer draw from his conclusion on ethical disputes?

A

We cannot bring forth superior moral judgements because they are just assertions and expressions of feelings.