Mill’s utilitarianism Flashcards

1
Q

mill’s utilitarianism

A

Mill disagrees with Bentham on the basis that only the amount of pleasure matters whereas all pleasures are measured of equal value and disregards the quality of pleasure.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
2
Q

higher pleasure

pleasures of the mind such as:

A

o Poetry
o Maths
o Art
o Music

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
3
Q

Lower pleasures

pleasures of the body such as:

A
o	Food
o	Drink
o	Sex
o	Drugs
o	Sleep

We need to achieve the lower pleasures to have access to the higher pleasures.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
4
Q

Relation between higher and lower pleasure:

A

Mill argues that, if our physical needs are met, people will prefer the pleasures of thought, feeling and imagination to pleasures of the body and the senses, even if our ‘higher’ capacities mean we can experience terrible pain, boredom and dissatisfaction.

appreciating the higher pleasures can be more demanding.

Our ability to experience higher pleasures can be undermined by hard work, lack of time, infrequent opportunities to experience them, and etc.

We may seek lower pleasures simply because those are more readily available to us.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
5
Q

question+answers of pleasure

decide which pleasure to persuade?

A

we need to consult people who know what they are talking about.

Having been to an art gallery once doesn’t count as having experienced the pleasures of art and listening to just one pop song doesn’t count as having experienced the pleasures of pop music.

Mill says that one pleasure is higher than another if almost everyone who is ‘competently acquainted’ with both prefers one over the other.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
6
Q

criticism - does it make sense still from a hedonistic pov?

A

is it still hedonistic utilitarianism? the distinction means some pleasures can be better but bring less pleasure. if this is the case we are no longer seeking to maximise pleasure.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
7
Q

response- red isn’t blue

A

mill may be claiming that higher and lower pleasures are simply not comparable and are not measured to the same standard ie lower pleasures are not less pleasant than higher pleasures.

red is not blue. no matter how red it is there will be no blue. they are simply different.

we can only seek someone who has experienced both and ask which is better or worse.

mill also doesn’t see happiness just as a question of pleasure. human have the capacity to reason and develop

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
8
Q

criticism- loses simplicity

A

what makes utiliatarism so appealing is its simplicity.
weighting up the pleasures and subtracting the pain

when mill introduced the notion of quality some of the simplicity disappeared.

library= 10 gyms?

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
9
Q

criticism- elitism

A

cultural elitism

argued that the term- higher pleasures = the things that mill and his finds like to do.
snobbishly dismissive of the pleasures of the masses.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
10
Q

Nozick’s experience machine

A

imagine being faced with the chance of plugging into a virtual reality machine.

This machine will produce the experience of a very happy life, not only with many and various pleasures and few pains but (the experience of) many successful achievements.

if we plug in, we will not know that we are in a virtual reality machine. We will believe that what we experience is reality. However, we must agree to plug in for life or not at all.

Nozick argues that most of us would not plug in.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
11
Q

Explanation <3

A

We value being in contact with reality, even if that makes us less happy, even if we experience fewer achievements.

what we want is not a psychological state at all; it is a relation to something outside our minds.

we want achievements; but we want real achievements, not just the psychological state of experiencing an achievement.

Nozick concludes that we cannot understand what is good just in terms of our subjective psychological states, such as pleasure.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
12
Q

criticisms of the pleasure machine

list

A

it isn’t pleasure we seek but state of affairs in the world things outside our heads
it isn’t pleasure that we seek but the specific actions activities and objects themselves
pleasure is a way of talking about behaviour not sensations

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
13
Q

it isnt pleasure we seek but states of affairs in the world things outside our heads

A
  • what people often want is a state of affairs in the world, they want their children to be happy, or for people to think well of them, or for there to be more dolphins.
  • People want states of affairs not for the sensations that might then result in their heads, if it was sensations, we’re after, then surely we would step into the machine, but many wont, as what they seek are things in the real world and not sensations and deceptions.
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
14
Q

it isnt pleasure that we seek but the specific actions activities and objects themselves

A
  • imagine collecting stickers, you’re missing one and have been trying to get it for ages, you really want it. Bentham would claim that the sticker is just a means to your ultimate aim, which is the pleasure it will give you. However, you may feel strongly that what you actually want is the sticker, not the pleasure it will give.
  • But if I offered to give you something of equal amount of pleasure that you would gain from getting the missing sticker, but some another source ie unreleased music, then you might be tempted but would still probably claim that it is the sticker you want, not just a certain quantity of pleasure.
  • Henry Sidwick claimed that it is the specific activities/objects in life that we desire and not pleasure itself. I might want to play volleyball for the intrinsic qualities of the game, the squeak of the floors, the impact of blocks, etc not for any specific sensation called pleasure.
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
15
Q

pleasure is a way of talking about behaviour not sensations.

A
  • We gain pleasure from lots of things: anime, good music, vibe sess. These are all things I seek to do but there doesn’t seem to be a specific mental sensation linking them all. Behaviourists and others would claim that pleasure isn’t a specific sensation, instead they claim it’s a way of talking collectively about all of those things that we seek to do ie calling things pleasurable= what we seek.If this is true then he psychological hedonism theory is empty, if we can define pleasure as what we seek then the sentence, we seek pleasure means we seeks what we seek which is a tautology (true by definition) and tells us nothing new about the world, this may be why Bentham, thought it was always possible to show that we seek pleasure- because its true by definition.
  • Is not clear that pleasure is a mental sensation or a way of talking about activities we prefer to do because some utilitarians believe that we should focus on satisfying people’s preferences rather than maximising their pleasure.
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
16
Q

mill’s proof of the greatest happiness principle

A

Step 1: from desired to desirable
1 the only evidence that something is visible is that it can actually be seen
2 similarly the only evidence that something is desirable i that it is actually desired
3 each person desires their own happiness

Step 2: from individual happiness to general happiness being desirable
4 therefore each person’s happiness is desirable
5 the general happiness is desirable
6 each person’s happiness is a good to that person
7 the general happiness is a good to the aggregate of all persons
(Mill is saying here that if happiness is good to you as an individual then the general happiness is good to the aggregate (sum) of all people. )

Step 3 happiness as the sole end/ criteria for morality
8 happiness is the only good.

17
Q

explanation

Dumbed down for me <3

A

Part 1: Mill argues that you can’t strictly ‘prove’ that something is good or not. That is, it is not something that you can deduct from other premises. This is normal for ‘first principles’ in any area of knowledge, and a claim about what is ultimately good is a first principle in ethics. Nonetheless, we can give a reasoned argument about what is good.

Part 2 The claim that happiness is good is relatively uncontroversial. It is much more controversial to claim that it is the only good. Mill must argue that everything of value – truth, beauty, freedom, etc. – derives its value from happiness. But clearly, people desire many different things. Of course, we may desire many things as a means to happiness. Happiness has many ‘ingredients’, such as truth and freedom, and each ingredient is desirable in itself. But everything we desire is a means to happiness. e.g., we want truth (being in touch with reality) and not because it has some psychological effect on us.

18
Q

criticism equivocation

A

mill suggest the property of being desirable is like the property of being visible. however it can be argued that desirability is crucially different as it has two meanings

sense1- a factual sense meaning that which is able to be desired (which could be anything - even morally questionable things)

sense2- a more moral sense meaning that which ought to be desired

The mistake of identifying “what is actually desired” with “what ought to be desired”
We all agree that:
- Visible= “able to be seen”
- Audible= “able to be heard”

But desired doesn’t mean “able to be desired”

Usually when we say something is desirable, we are recommending it as something that is fit or worthy to be desired, something that we ought to desire. So, there are two senses of the word desire.

mill is using desired in sense 1- people do desire happiness to suggest happiness is morally desirable in sense 2.

19
Q

defence

A

he’s not trying to deuce by definition that anything we desire is worthy or desire. Mill is an empiricist so believes that only experience is capable of telling us what is desirable. All we have is the evidence of what humans actually desire. No one would be conceived that something was a suitable goal, unless it was already in practice a goal.

20
Q

criticism- the is ought gap

A
  • Mill is open to a criticism that you can’t argue for morality on the basis of actual behaviour or experience- you can’t say how we should behave just on the basis on how we do ie owning slaves.
  • Suggested by Hume, Hume claims that many moral thinkers start their argument by discussing what is the case in the world (making factual claims) and then end up concluding what ought to be the case in the world (making prescriptive/ moral claims).
  • Hume suggest that moving from an is to an ought always involves a logical error.
21
Q

criticism- Naturalistic fallacy

A

Moore’s points involve that claim that the term good is indefinable and any attempt to equate good with a property in the natural world (such as happiness) is a mistake.
- If ‘good’ literally meant ‘happiness’, then it would be a meaningless question to ask if happiness is always good.
And it is not a meaningless question.

22
Q

defence

A

Warnock argues that mill does not attempt top define desirable or good, he is simply setting out for us what sort of things are as a matter of fact considered good. mill is trying to persuade us of the truth of utilitarianism by informing us that people already consider happiness to good (and desirable).
E.g., If people considered pain to be fundamentally desirable then it would be, mill is an empiricist and basing his argument on evidence alone.

23
Q

Criticism: fallacy of the composition

A

Mill argue that general happiness is desirable (5) because each person desire their own happiness (3).
- But who is it who desires the general happiness? You and me? It does not follow that if each person wants their own happiness, then each of us also wants the general happiness.
This known as the fallacy of composition- juts because something applies to each part, it doesn’t necessarily apply to the whole as well. E.g., each human has a mother but that doesn’t mean that humanity as a whole has a mother.
So, it doesn’t follow that general happiness is desirable to each individual, perhaps the general happiness is desirable to the general people the collective us, but the collective us is not the sort of thing that has desires. This same point arises in arguing that because happiness is a good for each of us that (8) the general happiness is a good to the aggregate of all persons (7).

24
Q

explanation of the last premise- happiness as the ultimate end

A

Mill relies on the principle of psychological association.
- The claim is that we are don’t naturally or originally desire things such as money, after all for a baby money is just a kind of funny paper. It is only through culture and socialisation that we come to see money initially as a means to happiness, then as a constituent part of this happiness.

  • In this what money can become an end itself (for some people) not initially but through its association with happiness. As such, we should see happiness as the ultimate end.