Midterm Flashcards

1
Q

Normative

A

Claims/questions about what ought to be the case. Typically settled by authority and/or reason. Characteristic of theology, philosophy, ordinary socialization.
 Humes law: can’t validly derive a normative claim from descriptive premises

 Law, morality, etiquette, and religion (at least in the Abrahamic religions) are all normative (prescriptive) domains—they involve “thou shalt” and “thou shalt not” precepts.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
2
Q

Descriptive

A

claims/questions about what is the case. Typically settled (at least supposedly) by empirical data. The kind of questions/claims typical of science
o You can definitely settle a descriptive question in principle.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
3
Q

Distinguishing Law & Morality (Descriptive)

A

 On either view, it is clear that morality and (human-made) law are not necessarily identical (at least not descriptively)

 Coordination Problems: Many actions that are governed by law (e.g., in Canada, driving on the right side of the road rather than the left) are presumably matters of indifference from a moral point of view

 (In this respect, coordination problems are analogous to some matters of etiquette)

Laws that are not moral satisfy coordination problems

What you choose doesn’t matter, the fact that you chose is what matters.

Laws that are in place to solve coordination problems are not moral laws but laws of moral indifference.
Ex, we could have chosen different colors for stop lights (red, yellow, green).

Law and morality on one hand can’t be identical because there are laws that are concerned with moral indifference.

Wedding rings solve a coordination problem.

 Immoral Laws: On the other hand, many practices have been inscribed in law, that are, if anything is, clearly immoral.

 E.g. slavery, forced sterilization of the disabled, private recreational drug use or sexual behaviour.

 Conflicting Moral and Legal Duties: Similarly, there are often cases when legal and moral duties seem to conflict.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
4
Q

Legal Positivism

A

is the view that the existence and content of law depends on social facts and not on its moral or practical or political merits.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
5
Q

Bentham on Legal positivism (Utilitarian)

A

 Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832): A main proponent of both LP and utilitarian (U) moral theory. U (in a nutshell):

  1. Actions are morally right or wrong by virtue of the aggregate consequences that they give rise to. (consequentialism)
  2. Consequences are to be evaluated in terms of utility—i.e., their intrinsic value (for Bentham, pleasure and pain)
  3. Everyone’s utility counts and counts equally (“each is to count for one, none for more than one”)
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
6
Q

Austin on legal positivism (Utilitarian)

A

 John Austin (1790-1859): “The existence of law is one thing; its merit and demerit another. Whether it be or be not is one enquiry; whether it be or be not conformable to an assumed standard, is a different enquiry” The Province of Jurisprudence Determined (1832).

 For Austin, positive law (of the sort that jurisprudence (theory/philosophy of law) concerns itself with):

 A general (as opposed to specific or individual) command, backed up with sanctions if not compiled with.

 Issued by a sovereign, who/which, by definition, receives habitual obedience from most of the population, but who does not habitually obey any other (earthly) person or institution. (“Uncommanded commanders,” 31)

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
7
Q

General elements of legal positivism

A
  1. Separability: Law and morality are conceptually distinct.
  2. Pedigree Thesis: Legal validity is ultimately a function of certain kinds of publicly ascertainable social facts, e.g., about which persons/institutions have the power to make, amend, or adjudicate law.

It counts as a valid law depending on how it came about, has to publicly ascertainable facts. Doesn’t have to be ascertainable by the public at large, but by a member of the public.

  1. Conventionality: Legal validity can ultimately be explained in terms of criteria that are authoritative by virtue of social convention (i.e., social facts about what people take to be authoritative)

What makes it a natural law is that people accept it as authoritative (has to do with social facts).

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
8
Q

Hart on legal positivism

A

 Hart’s view of legal positivism is that law and morality are distinct modes of social ordering.

For Utilitarians like Bentham and Austin, this is where a view (like NL) that links law and morality is apt to create two symmetrical sorts of danger…

They want you to obey the law because it promotes Utilitarianism. They want you to be obeyed punctually because if a law does not maximize happiness criticize it until it does, not all laws are moral. Criticize the law in the hope of reform, criticize the law in the hope for amendment.

Hart says there’s two dangers of morality and law heavily coinciding—makes it heavily immune from moral criticism and makes people reject it if they don’t think its moral

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
9
Q

Legal realism

A

 In the broadest terms, LR is the view that “what is the law?” and “how does the law function?”, etc., are fundamentally empirical questions.

 Accordingly, LR (of all species) holds that law can and should be investigated using the (allegedly) value-free methods characteristic of the natural sciences

 In that respect, LR is clearly opposed to NL and in accord with the LP separability thesis.

 But LR also identifies in NL and LP (in general) a shared object of criticism…

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
10
Q

Legal Formalism

A

 LF (descriptive sense) is the idea that the determination of what is/is not the law (the determination of standards of legal validity) is essentially a matter of inference from principles.

 LF (normative sense) is the idea that judges should adjudicate by (inferentially) applying established legal principles to the specific cases in front of them.

 Compare: The claim/presumption in common law systems that judges are not making law but finding it

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
11
Q

Formalism

A

 ….i.e., judges may maintain that, in adjudicating cases, they are deductively applying uncontroversial legal principles to the facts of a particular case.

 (I.e., ‘rules of law’ are like [true] premises in a deductive argument which, together with [true] factual premises about the facts of the case determine the conclusion/judgement).

 Note: The formalist perspective implies (or pretends) that the law is essentially clear, consistent, and complete.

  1. PQ
  2. P_____
  3. Therefore, Q
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
12
Q

Prediction theory

A

 A precursor of American LR: SCOTUS Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes (1897):

 “The prophecies of what the courts will do in fact, and nothing more pretentious, are what I mean by the law”

The law is about predictions about what the courts will do in fact

 I.e., the law is simply what is decided by the courts.

There is a problem because there is not a separation of powers from a jurisprudence perspective. Judges could be corrupted. There’s no such thing as rules governing the behaviours of the legal system.

 A “bad man… does not care two straws” about morality or legal principles. He is interested simply in the prediction—‘if I do this, what will the likely consequences be?’ (A pragmatist view)

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
13
Q

Statutory Lawlessness

A

 Radbruch: Being properly promulgated as law (LP: “pedigree”; Hart: being included under a ‘rule of recognition’) is a fundamental importance but cannot in and of itself guarantee legal validity.
 Hitler, e.g., gained power in an ostensibly legal manner and the Nazi regime promulgated any number of “laws” that were flagrantly unjust and/or immoral.
 For the positivist, “a law is a law”—‘statutory lawlessness’ and ‘supra-statutory law’ are both a “contradiction in terms” (127)…

 …positivism “claims to have proved the validity of a statute simply by showing that the statute had sufficient power behind it to prevail. But while power may indeed serve as a basis for the ‘must’ of compulsion, it never serves as the basis for the ‘ought’ of obligation or for legal validity” (131, emphasis added)
 For Radbruch, certain Nazi laws show that there are supra-statutory conditions against which a law can be tested: extreme injustice is no law—even appropriately enacted and socially effective norms lose their legal validity when they are extremely unjust

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
14
Q

The Radbruch Formula

A

 Radbruch: Legal validity must be based “a value inherent in the statute” (132).

Which statutes add up to the legal validity of that statute

 Which values are relevant?

  1. Legal certainty: Any statute is better than no statute
  2. Purposiveness: Serves the public benefit
  3. Justice: Protects (especially) equality under the law.

The “Formula”

  1. “Intolerability”
  2. “Disavowel”

So in other words:

  1. A properly promulgated positive statute is a presumptively legally valid, up to the point at which it is (objectively) in ‘intolerable’ conflict with justice. Past that point, the validity of the statute must ‘yield’ to justice.
  2. But, a statute which has the intention or purpose to betray justice is not law at all. Presumably, this entails knowing subjectively the intentions of legislators…

 Radbruch implies that positivism (i.e., positivistic attitudes among lawyers and juries) had in fact been an important enabler of the Nazi regime
 It left “both jurists and the people defenseless against just such arbitrary, cruel, and criminal statute”.
 The Radbruch formula is intended to provide jurists with “weapons against a recurrence of such an unjust state”.
 But, not: Radbruch’s view is a curious form of NL (Dyzenhaus: “positivism with a minus sign”)—legal certainty trumps injustice except where the injustice is ‘intolerable’

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
15
Q

Fuller’s Principles of Legality

A

 P1: rules must be expressed in general terms;
 P2: Rules must be publicly promulgated;
 P3: Rules must be prospective in effect;
 P4: Rules must be expressed in understandable terms;
 P5: Rules must be consistent with one another;
 P6: Rules must not require conduct beyond the powers of the affected parties;
 P7: Rules must not be changed so frequently that the subject cannot rely on them;
 P8: Rules must be administered in a manner consistent with their wording.

 Fuller: These principles of legality are, in effect, existence conditions for a legal system.
 We can know these principles because, according to Fuller, we can know the fundamental purposes of law: to subject “human conduct to the governance of rules”. The rule of law attains it authority insofar as it furthers these (moral) purposes.
 For Hart, recall, the law draws on morality if moral principles are incorporated into rules of recognition. Conceptually, the authority of the law is like the authority of a rules in a game.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
16
Q

Primary rules (rules of conduct)

A

 Rules that require or prohibit certain kinds of behaviour; which create legal obligations and provide for sanctions when they are disobeyed.

 Minimally, primary rules will include the usual “restrictions on the free use of violence, theft, and deception to which human beings are tempted, but which they must, in general, repress” (53)

17
Q

Secondary rules (empowering rules)

A

 These defects are remedied by what Hart terms secondary rules: i.e., ‘meta’ rules that are about primary rules (the presence of which distinguish a proper legal system from a primitive ‘pre-legal’ system)

  1. Rules of Recognition: Remedy uncertainty by specifying “some feature or features possession of which by a suggested rule is taken as a conclusive affirmative indication that it is a rule of the group to be supported by the social pressure it exerts” (56, emphasis added).

 2. Rules of Change: Remedy the problem of static rules by providing mechanisms to add, remove, or modify primary or secondary rules.
Could be legislative change—new government. Change in attitudes. Change in sanctions—too costly to imprison some people. Change in morals

 3.Rules of Adjudication: remedy inefficiency by empowering individuals or bodies to make authoritative determinations concerning when or whether, on a particular occasion, a primary rule has been violated.

18
Q

Prediction theory

A

 A precursor of American LR: SCOTUS Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes (1897):

 “The prophecies of what the courts will do in fact, and nothing more pretentious, are what I mean by the law”

The law is about predictions about what the courts will do in fact

 A “bad man… does not care two straws” about morality or legal principles. He is interested simply in the prediction—‘if I do this, what will the likely consequences be?’ (A pragmatist view)

 …For Holmes, though, the purpose of the law is the prevention of bad social consequences/furtherance of good social consequences.

 Formalist “mechanical jurisprudence” simply disguises or obscures the goals that motivate the behaviour of legal officials.

19
Q

The Candour Argument

A

 …this was taken to be a triumph of NLL: The 1934 statute was held to be unlawful (being ‘contrary to the sense of justice of all decent human beings’), despite its formally valid pedigree.
 Hart: This is “hysteria” (45). In 1949 the judges actually faced a choice between a) letting the wife go unpunished for a flagrantly immoral act and b) acting pursuant to a frankly retrospective law
 Hart: It is “romantic optimism” to assume that “all values that we cherish ultimately will fit into a single system” (46).
 As Austin and Bentham held, law may be law, but at the same time some laws may be too evil to be obeyed.
 Re: Fuller—Disputes about the “essential” character of law come to resemble “disputes about whether chess could still be ‘chess’ if played without pawns” (47).
 If by “essential” we simply mean essential in light of certain contingent facts, this is understandable and possibly useful:
 ‘No legal system that utterly failed to satisfy X has ever existed or could ever exist’

20
Q

Problems of the Penumbra

A

 Consider a rule which forbids taking a vehicle into a public park. What counts as a ‘vehicle’ for the purposes of applying the rule (assuming this isn’t explicitly set out)”? Automobiles, plainly, says Hart. But what about bicycles, roller skates, and aeroplanes?

 Hart: If we are to use words at all (in legal or non-legal contexts), there must be a “core of settled meaning”–I.e., some accepted, standard cases of what words mean.

 But there will also be a penumbra of “debatable cases in which words are neither obviously applicable and/or (check textbook, word missing) not obviously ruled out”

 …the penumbra shows that judicial decision making can’t be a matter of deduction alone (as LF asserts and LR denies). Instead, it indicates that judges, when faced with uncertainty in hard cases, must make a decision.

21
Q

Fuller’s principle of legality

A

 P1: rules must be expressed in general terms;
 P2: Rules must be publicly promulgated;
 P3: Rules must be prospective in effect;
 P4: Rules must be expressed in understandable terms;
 P5: Rules must be consistent with one another;
 P6: Rules must not require conduct beyond the powers of the affected parties;
 P7: Rules must not be changed so frequently that the subject cannot rely on them;
 P8: Rules must be administered in a manner consistent with their wording.

 Fuller: These principles of legality are, in effect, existence conditions for a legal system.
 We can know these principles because, according to Fuller, we can know the fundamental purposes of law: to subject “human conduct to the governance of rules”. The rule of law attains it authority insofar as it furthers these (moral) purposes.
 For Hart, recall, the law draws on morality if moral principles are incorporated into rules of recognition. Conceptually, the authority of the law is like the authority of a rules in a game.

22
Q

Hart on the Command View

A

 The idea that law is a command is “breathtaking in its simplicity and quite inadequate” (31).

 Consider: A gunman says, “your money or your life”. If the gunman says this to a large number of people who are accustomed to shake-downs and who habitually surrender to them, he’d be acting like an (Austinian) legal system.

 Hart: “Law surely is not the gunman situation writ large, and legal order is surely not to be thus simply identified with compulsion” (32).

The threat of sanction in real life is coercive sanction (going to jail, charges, etc.)

Hart thinks we obey the law because it deserves/should be obeyed.

Raw power as a method of exercising control is expensive and unstable (gunman could fall asleep and compliance of the gunman would go down)

 According to Hart, the simple idea of “law as command” might be applicable to a monarch who has reigned long enough for the habit of obedience to develop.

 But this fails to explain the continuity of legal systems.

 Moreover, in a democracy, the sovereign presumably at least partly consistent of the (constantly changing) body of electors who vote for their agents in the legislature.

 But then who/what is outside of the law to be habitually obeyed? Presumably, the (sovereign) population is habitually obeying itself…

23
Q

Hart on the Concept of Law

A
  • So, in short, Hart rejects Austin’s command view. But what, the, is legal validity, according to Hart?
  • Hart’s account hangs on the distinction between primary and secondary rules
24
Q

Primary Rules (Rules of Conduct) (Hart):

A

 Rules that require or prohibit certain kinds of behaviour; which create legal obligations and provide for sanctions when they are disobeyed.

 Minimally, primary rules will include the usual “restrictions on the free use of violence, theft, and deception to which human beings are tempted, but which they must, in general, repress” (53)

 Some (most) people comply with the primary rules because they feel or believe that they are obligated to comply (i.e., because they accept the rules as authoritative from an internal perspective)

 Others, however, may “reject the rules except where fear of social pressure induces them to conform” (54). Though (at least in small, simple society) these people must comprise only a minority (otherwise sanctions would be ineffective)…

25
Q

Defects for primary rules (Hart)

A

“Defects”
 Such a ‘pre-legal’ society is possible, but it could not be said to have a proper legal system and would suffer from certain defects.
1. Uncertainty: No procedure for authoritatively determining what is or is not the law
2. Static: No means for adapting the law to changing circumstances
3. Inefficiency: No means for authoritatively determining when the law has (or has not) been violated; no monopoly on sanctions.

26
Q

Secondary Rules (Empowering rules)

A

 These defects are remedied by what Hart terms secondary rules: i.e., ‘meta’ rules that are about primary rules (the presence of which distinguish a proper legal system from a primitive ‘pre-legal’ system)

  1. Rules of Recognition: Remedy uncertainty by specifying “some feature or features possession of which by a suggested rule is taken as a conclusive affirmative indication that it is a rule of the group to be supported by the social pressure it exerts” (56, emphasis added).

 2. Rules of Change: Remedy the problem of static rules by providing mechanisms to add, remove, or modify primary or secondary rules.
Could be legislative change—new government. Change in attitudes. Change in sanctions—too costly to imprison some people. Change in morals

 These may concern the powers of persons

 Hart: There is a necessarily close connection ‘between rules of change and rules of recognition: Where rules of recognition exist they “will necessarily incorporate reference to legislation as an identifying feature of rules”

 3.Rules of Adjudication: remedy inefficiency by empowering individuals or bodies to make authoritative determinations concerning when or whether, on a particular occasion, a primary rule has been violated.

 Hart: There is also a close connection between rules of adjudication and rules of recognition—an authorized determination of when rules have been broken “cannot avoid being taken as [an] authoritative determination of what the rules are” (58

27
Q

Hart’s definition of the law

A

 Hart: “the union of primary and secondary rules”

Formalized:
 A rule R is legally valid in a society S if and only if (and because) it satisfies the criteria of validity contained in a rule of recognition that is accepted as binding in S.

 A rule of recognition is binding in S if and only if (and because) there is a social convention among officials to regard it as defining standards of official behaviour.

What’s binding? Rules of recognition are fundamental because it is conventionally accepted among officials.

 Note the idea of “official behaviour”
 Hart: It is a minimum necessary condition for the existence of legal system that its valid rules of behaviour be generally obeyed (64). But how?

 When it comes to primary rules, (some, many) ordinary individuals may comply with the law “for his part only” (i.e., out of fear of sanctions—the ‘external perspective)…