mens rea Flashcards

You may prefer our related Brainscape-certified flashcards:
1
Q

when is a defendant taken to have intended a result?

A
  • if it was his/her aim or purpose, and
  • if the result was foreseen as virtually certain to occur as a result of the defendant’s actions and
  • the defendant realised this
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
2
Q

when will defendants be found to be reckless?

A

if they appreciated that because of their actions there was a chance that the result might occur, and it was unreasonable for them to act as they did

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
3
Q

when will a defendant be found to be negligent?

A

if she/he behaved in a way that a reasonable person would not. it is rare for negligence to count as sufficient mens rea

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
4
Q

what happens if a defendant is found to be voluntarily intoxicated?

A

the defendant will be found to have been reckless. if, though intoxicated, the defendant intended the result, s/he will still be held to have the requisite mens rea

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
5
Q

what is the definition of intention?

A

normal meaning - purpose/aim.

  • Lord Bridge in R v Moloney (1985)
  • R v Wright (2000)
  • R v Ogunbowale (2007)

but in exceptional borderline cases the jury can be directed that they are entitled to find intention if a result was virtually certain to occur and the defendant realised it was virtually certain to occur

  • R v Hales (2005)
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
6
Q

jury will need to be persuaded beyond reasonable doubt

A

R v Haigh (2010) - clear evidence D had smothered her child, but no evidence as to how or in what circumstances she had done this. because it wasn’t clear beyond reasonable doubt that she had murdered her child, she could only be found guilty of manslaughter and not murder

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
7
Q

what is the test for seeing whether a result was the purpose of the defendant?

A

Antony Duff’s test of failure: had the result not occured, would the defendant regard himself as having failed in his plan?

  • but where a result is a means to achieve a desired end, it has to be treated with caution
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
8
Q

what should intention be distinguished from?

A

foresight, motive and premeditation

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
9
Q

distinguishing intention and foresight

A
  • in relation to core meaning - whether the defendant’s act was likely to produce the consequence is irrelevant
  • but many commentators also accept that if the defendant believes that it is impossible for his action to cause the result, he cannot be said to intend it, however much he may have wanted the result to occur
  • foresight of a consequence is not the same as intention, but it is evidence from which a jury may infer or find intention
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
10
Q

Lord Scarman in *Hancock and Shankland *(1986)

A

the greater the probability of a consequence the more likely it is that the consequence was foreseen and…if that consequence was foreseen the greater the probability is that the consequence was also intended…[T]he probability, however high, of a consequence is only a factor

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
11
Q

distinguishing intention and motive

A

Moloney (1985): “intention is something quite different from motive or desire”

  • possible to intend something without wanting it to happen, and having foreseen it
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
12
Q

Hales (2005)

A

D ran over a police officer in his car in attempting to escape from an arrest - not his motive to kill the police officer, but he was (as Keene LJ explained) “prepared to kill in order to escape” and therefore intended to kill

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
13
Q

intention and premeditation

A

a person can act instinctively in the heat of the moment and yet intend to kill - shouldn’t be thought that a person can intend a result only if s/he has carefully formulated a plan as to how to produce that result

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
14
Q

Woollin (1999)

A

Confirms the Nedrick approach: to establish intent the defendant’s actions must have been virtually certain to have caused the consequence, and the defendant must have appreciated that such was the case.

  • jury may find indirect intention, i.e. the intention of the person who does not aim or need to kill or even to cause grievous bodily harm to anyone but nonetheless takes (what he knows to be) an outrageously high risk of doing so, if the result of the defendant’s action was virtually certain to be death or grievous bodily harm (objective test), and the defendant personally foresaw this (subjective test)
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
15
Q

what is the chart for deciding whether a defendant has intention?

A

was it the result of the defendant’s purpose?

  • yes: he intended it
  • no: move to the next question

was the result a virtually certain result of his actions and did the defendant realise that the result was a virtually certain result of his actions?

  • no: he didn’t intend the result
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
16
Q

problems with Woollin

A
  • must the jury find intention, or may the jury find intention? e.g. Court of Appeal in Matthews (2003) made it clear that it was a misdirection for a judge to tell a jury that if a result was foreseen as virtually certain then they must find intention, but then went on to say that there would be certain situations (including the case itself) where it wold be “irresistable” for the jury
  • jury can take any factor they deem relevant into account (but isn’t this throwing the scope a little too wide?)
  • Lord Steyn provides no justification for his changing of the word ‘infer’ to ‘find’ - why?
  • does Woollin apply to just murder, or to all crimes requiring proof of intention?
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
17
Q

Moloney (1985)

A
  • D and stepfather engaged on long drinking spree - then decided to engage in a shooting competition to see who could load and fire a gun the fastest - D won, but in so doing shot his stepfather dead
  • held not guilty for murder (but for manslaughter). defence in this case wasn’t the intoxication, but that he lacked mens rea (of which the intoxication was evidence)
  • established that a person can have intention, where they did not want the result but merely foresaw it.
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
18
Q

Cunningham recklessness

A
  1. the defendant was aware that there was a risk that his/her conduct would cause a particular result AND
  2. the risk was an unreasonable one for the defendant to take

Byrne J: “the accused has foreseen that the particular kind of harm might be done and yet has gone on to take the risk of it”

note that the risk doesn’t have to be obvious to the reasonable man - just the defendant. recall Stephenson (1979) - schizophrenic man set fire to a haystack, but because of his illness he didn’t realise that in lighting a match there would be danger to the haystack

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
19
Q

R v Parker (1977)

A

upheld R v Briggs (1977), amending definition to say “a man is reckless in the sense required when he carries out a deliberate act knowing or closing his mind to the obvious fact that there is some risk of damage arising from that act but nevertheless continuing in performance of that act”

Lane LJ: “in the view of this court, that type of action, that type of deliberate closing of the mind, is the equivalent of knowledge and a man certainly cannot escape the consequences of his actions in this particular set of circumstances by saying ‘i never directed my mind to the obvious consequences because i was in a self-induced state of temper’”

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
20
Q

Brady (2007)

A

affirmed that it’s merely enough for the defendant to have foreseen *a *risk, didn’t necessarily have to be obvious and significant

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
21
Q

Caldwell recklessness

A

will be guilty if

  1. aware of a risk OR
  2. there was an obvious and serious risk AND they failed to consider whether or not there was a risk

approved in R v Lawrence (1982), but confirmed abolished by Attorney-General’s Reference (No 3 of 2003)

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
22
Q

difference between cunningham and caldwell

A

caldwell included defendants who weren’t aware of an obvious risk - punished those who failed to notice a risk which would’ve been obvious to a reasonable person

  • unfairly penalises those who fail to appreciate a risk they are incapable of foreesing
    • Elliot v C (1983)
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
23
Q

R v G and R (2003)

A

defendant must be shown to have subjectively appreciated a risk to the health or property of another but carried on in any event before they may be said to be criminally culpable. It abolished the “objective recklessness” test previously established under R v Caldwell

Bingham saw the need to modify Lord Diplock’s definition to take account of the defence of infancy, which contains the concept of “mischievous discretion”. This rule requires the court to consider the extent to which children of eight or more years are able to understand the difference between “right” and “wrong”. The Diplock test of obviousness might operate unfairly for 11- and 12-year-old boys if they were held to the same standard as reasonable adults. Bingham stated that “a person acts ‘recklessly’ with respect to:

(i) a circumstance when he is aware of a risk that it exists or will exist;
(ii) a result when he is aware of a risk that it will occur
and it is, in the circumstances known to him, unreasonable to take the risk.”

This brings the test back to a subjective standard so that defendants can be judged on the basis of their age, experience and understanding rather than on the standard of a hypothetical reasonable person who might have better knowledge and understanding.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
24
Q

alternatives to caldwell and cunningham

A
  1. defendants would be reckless if they are awake of a risk or failed to consider a risk which should have been obvious to a reasonable person of their age and mental abilities
  2. defendants would be reckless if they were aware of a risk or failed to consider an obvious risk without a good explanation –> acquittal of those who failed to see a risk due to an illness or emergency, but lead to the conviction of those who failed to see the risk due to drunkenness or anger
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
25
Q

problems with R v G and R

A
  • too easy for a defendant to claim that they didn’t consider a risk to others and so be entitled to acquittal
  • confirmed the rules relating to intoxication - whereby a defendant who is voluntary intoxicated can be convicted without awareness of the risk. HL presented the intoxication rules as a special exception to the nromal requirement of having to prove a subjective state of mind, but given the number of crimes committed by intoxicated people it seems like the norm rather than exception
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
26
Q

negligence

A

if the defendant behaved in a way which a reasonable person would not

  • uses an objective test - defendant’s state of mind not relevant in deciding whether the defendant is negligent, and there’s no need to show the defendant intended/foresaw a risk
  • what matters is conduct
27
Q

problems with the meaning of negligence

A
  1. what if the defendant acts out of panic/fear?
  2. is the standard expected of the person ‘reasonable’/’ordinary’?
  3. what if the defendant is unable to act in accordance with the standard of the reasonable person?
  4. is it possible to expect the defendant to show a higher standard of behaviour than that expected of the reasonable person?
28
Q

gross negligence

A

in relation to manslaughter - show defendant killed negligently and this negligence was so bad as to justify a criminal conviction

29
Q

distinguishing between intention, recklessness and negligence

A

boundary between intention and recklessness

  • Woollin direction: cases where a result was not the defendant’s purpose but it was foreseen as virtually certain

boundary between recklessness and negligence

  • whether result was foreseen vs whether acted as a reasonable person would
  • but - consider Parker (1977)
30
Q

intoxication and intent

A
  1. if the drunken D had as his purpose the result he intended it, according to Majewski (1977), “a drunken intent is still an intent”
  2. if the drunken D lacked intent he is not guilty of an intent-based crime, although he may be guilty of a recklessness based offence
31
Q

in what ways can intoxication be relevant to a criminal case?

A
  1. D may for some crimes seek to rely on his intoxication as evidence that he lacked mens rea
  2. prosecution may in some crimes seek to rely on D’s intoxication to establish D’s mens rea
  3. some crimes specifically refer to being intoxicated, e.g. it is an offence to drive a vehicle under the influence of drink or drugs (Road Traffic Act 1988)
32
Q

voluntary intoxication

A

can introduce evidence of their intoxication to prove they lacked the mens rea in crimes of specific intent and are therefore not guilty

in crimes of basic intent the fact that they were intoxicated when they committed the crime will provide the evidence that they had the necessary mens rea

33
Q

involuntary intoxication

A

can introduce evidence of their intoxication to persuade the jury that they lacked the mens rea of the crime. if, however, the jury finds they had the mens rea they will be guilty; if they did not, they are not guilty

34
Q

knowledge requirement

A

involves a positive belief that a state of affairs exists. D who fears that circumstances may exist and deliberately decides not to make any further inquiries in case his/her suspicions prove to be well founded will be said to know the circumstances

35
Q

Forbes (Giles) (2001)

A

for cases where the mens rea is knowledge, careful consideration should be given to which aspects of the actus reus need to be known

36
Q

Grainge (1974)

A

knowledge requires a positive belief; a suspicion alone may not be enough

  • Reader (1977): belief that property may be stolen isn’t enough for a belief that it is stolen. doesn’t mean that D must be absolutely certain that circumstances exist - if s/he assumes a set of facts to be true and has no serious doubts about them, that state of mind amounts to knowledge
37
Q

doctrine of ‘wilful blindness’

A

if court decides that D was aware that there was a risk that the circumstances existed and deliberately decided not to make any further enquiries to find out whether his/her fears are true, then in effect the D is presumed to know the facts

38
Q

Westminster CC v Croyalgrange Ltd (1986)

A

“it is always open to the tribunal of fact, when knowledge on the part of a D is required to be proved, to base a finding of knowledge on evidence that D had deliberately shut his eyes to the obvious/refrained from enquiry because he suspected the truth but didn’t want to have his suspicions confirmed”

39
Q

transferred mens rea

A

often called doctrine of transferred malice (though misleading because it applies to any mens rea)

applies where a person aims to harm one person/piece of property but misses and harms another

  • Mitchell (1983)
40
Q

Attorney-General’s Reference (No 3 of 1994)(1998)

A

D stabbed pregnant girlfriend - child was born early as a result of the wound, and died from the wound - can D be charged with murder?

  • at time of stabbing the foetus was not a person in the eyes of the law
  • HL held not possible to transfer the intent to kill from the mother to the child who (at the time of the stabbing) didn’t exist as a legal person - but it can still be a criminal offence to kill a foetus, e.g. offence of procuring a miscarriage contrary to the Offences Against the Person Act 1861 s58
  • cannot transfer intent to kill/cause grievous bodily harm from girlfriend to child who actually died - would count as ‘double transfer’ (mother –> foetus, foetus –> person it would become in the future)
41
Q

Kay v Butterworth (1945)

A

example of how the actus reus and mens rea must coincide in order to find the defendant guilty

  • D is driving and begins to feel sleepy - decides to drive on rather than to stop for a rest - falls asleep at the wheel and kills a pedestrian
  • although at the time when he drove into the pedestrian he was acting involuntarily and so technically ‘not driving’ (he was an automaton), his careless driving caused him to fall into an involuntary state –> caused pedestrian’s injuries –> guilty of causing death by dangerous driving
42
Q

exceptions to coincidence rule

A
  • D may have mens rea at one point in time and then later (without mens rea) perform the actus reus
    • Meli v R (1954)
    • Le Brun (1991)
    • Lord Mustill in Attorney-General’s Reference (No 3 of 1994): the existence of an interval of time between the doing of an act by the defendant with the necessary wrongful intent and its impact on the victim in a manner which leads to death does not in itself prevent the intent, the act and the death from together amounting to murder, so long as there is an unbroken causal connection between the act and the death
  • D committed actus reus at one point in time (without the necessary mens rea) but at a later point in time has the mens rea
    • initial act should be seen as continuing act which is still continuing at the point in time the mens rea arises
    • D’s failure to stop the harm he was causing amounted to a criminal omission for which D should be convicted
      • R v Miller (1983)
  • unclear when actus reus occured
    • Attorney-General’s Reference (No 4 of 1980)
43
Q

A-G’s Reference (No 4 of 1980)

A

illustrates exception to coincidence requirement where unclear when the actus reus occured

  • D slapped girlfriend, pushed her down the stairs, put a rope around her neck, dragged her back up the stairs, cut her throat and cut her body into pieces. unclear which act caused her death, but clear one of them definitely had
  • held that as long as D had the necessary mens rea at the time of each of the possible acts that caused the death he could be properly convicted of murder/manslaughter
44
Q

Fagan v Metropolitan Police Commissioner (1969)

A

“it is not necessary that mens rea should be present at the inception of the actus reus; it can be superimposed on an existing act. on the other hand, the subsequent inception of mens rea cannot convert an act which has been completed without mens rea into an assault”

  • so while D’s acts might have been initially unintentional, the time came when, knowing the wheel was on the officer’s foot, he remained seated in the car so that his body through the medium of the car was in contact with the police officer, he switched off the ignition, maintained the wheel of the car on the foot and used words indicating the intention of keeping the wheel in that position […] there was an act constituting battery which at its inception wasn’t criminal because there was no element of intention, but which became criminal from the moment the intention was formed to produce the apprehension which was flowing from the continuing act
45
Q

what does the existence of mens rea show?

A

Kadish (1987): criminal law regards people as autonomous agents who are responsible for their actions/choices they make

46
Q

functions of mens rea

A
  1. ensures that censure correctly attaches to a criminal conviction (i.e. that D harmed V in a blameworthy way)
  2. ensures blameworthy people are convicted of the right offence (Brudner, 2008) e.g. distinction between murder and manslaughter
  3. helps define wrong done to the victim through identification of intent behind D’s actions
  4. ensures V is given fair warning of what is criminal (Chan and Simester, 2011)
  5. Chan and Simester: helps fight against over-criminalisation
47
Q

Baroness Wootton (1981)

A
  • proposed a legal system containing no mens rea requirements - argued criminal court wasn’t in a position to assess the blameworthiness of a defendant
  • offences should simply require proof that D harmed V - judge would be free to take into account D’s state of mind along with other relevant considerations at the sentencing stage
48
Q

cons of Wootton’s argument

A
  • have to accept that a person could be guilty of a crime even though s/he was entirely blameless for his/her actions
  • censuring effect of conviction would be lost
  • cannot assume anymore that a person found guilty of a crime was morally blameworthy
  • Evans 1987: if blameworthiness became irrelevant such a system could logically return to the practice (common in medieval law) of sentencing animals for criminal offences, i.e. if all you care about is conviction based on the consequences it could logically be possible to sentence an animal to death
49
Q

pros of Wootton’s argument

A
  • acknowledges harm done to the victim
    • e.g. rape victim - D’s state of mind (i.e. whether or not he knew she was consenting) doesn’t matter to him/her bc it doesn’t change the fact that s/he was raped
  • emphasises that we cannot be overconfident in the law’s ability to assess the blameworthiness of the D
50
Q

most serious criminal offences require proof of mens rea (B v DPP [2000])

A

there is a presumption that offences require proof of mens rea unless there is clear evidence rebutting that presumption

51
Q

choice theory

A

people are responsible for the things they chose to do; people should be guilty of a crime only if they chose effectively to do the actus reus

52
Q

capacity theory

A
  • similar to choice theory - accepts argument that people are responsible for what they chose to do
  • but also accepts it is proper to punish those who could have effectively chosen to act lawfully but didn’t
53
Q

character theory

A
  • D is responsible for his/her own character
  • if criminal actions reveal character traits that are opposed by the criminal law s/he should be punished
54
Q

how do the different theories suggest alternative understandings of mens rea?

A

choice

  • supports crimes based on intention and cunningham recklessness
  • wouldn’t support offences based on caldwell recklessness, negligence, or strict liability, where the D didn’t necessarily choose to commit a crime

capacity

  • also supports intention-based crimes and cunningham recklessness
  • but would also be willing to support criminal liability for inadvertence insofar as D could’ve appreciated the risk
  • would therefore support acquittal for Stephenson but not C (in Elliot v C)
  • would also allow some convictions to be based on negligence but only where D had the capacity of acting non-negligently
    • Moore (2000): suggests liability for negligence could be supported on the basis of unexercised capacity

character

  • allows for greater degree of distinguishment/identification of nuances in crime
55
Q

Brutus v Cozens (1973) (definition of mens rea)

A

words like ‘intention’ and ‘recklessness’ should carry their normal everyday meaning

  • but note objections to Lord Reid’s dicta?
56
Q

what makes intent the most serious form of mens rea?

A
  • Michael Moore (1997): an intended action is one where the actor seeks to control the action and its result in the sense used in moral assessment
  • Ferzan (2002): a person seeks to exert as great a control as possible over an action and its result where that action is intended
  • but - intended act can also be seen as simply the ideal conception of a voluntary act (Duff, 1990)
    • Gardner (1998): intention reflects not just a choice to act in a way which will lead to a result, but a wholehearted decision to act in order to bring a result about
57
Q

what are the four main views on intention? (note: names are given by Herring)

A
  1. ‘pure intention’ (Finnis, 1991)
  2. ‘moral elbow room’ view
  3. ‘oblique intention’
  4. ‘Hyam’
58
Q

‘pure intention’

A

promoted by those who argue that intention should mean purpose, nothing more/less

  • narrow view - popular with those who think it’s never justifiable to take someone else’s life
  • suggest that if we don’t like the conclusion we should just change the law on what the mens rea for [crime - usually murder] is rather than artificially stretch the law on intention
  • to intend to do [harmful thing] is to intend to kill them - consequences are inseparable (e.g. removing someone’s heart yet arguing you didn’t intend to kill)
  • support ‘ethical doctrine of double effect’
59
Q

doctrine of double effect (in relation to pure intention)

A

Keown: permissible to allow a bad consequence to result from one’ actions, even if it is foreseen to follow, provided certain conditions as identified by the principle of ‘double effect’ are satisfied:

  • act one’s engaged in is not itself bad
  • bad consequence isn’t a means to the good consequence
  • bad consequence is foreseen but not intended AND
  • there’s a sufficiently serious reason for allowing the bad consequence to occur (this requires jury to make a moral assessment of what D did)
60
Q

‘moral elbow room’ view (as appears in Horder, 1995)

A
  • intention is purpose, but where a D is aware that a result is virtually certain to follow from his actions the jury should be given a discretion to decide whether the mental state is wicked enough to be called intention
  • but test would produce too much uncertainty
    • different juries would reach different conclusions on different facts –> inconsistent verdicts
61
Q

‘oblique intention’

A

result which is foreseen as virtually certain is simply intended

62
Q

‘hyam’

A
  • if a result is foreseen as likely, then it is intended
  • had support of majority of HL in Hyam but has few supporters now
  • but if foresight of a result is intention then the boundary between intention and recklessness becomes blurred
63
Q

Williams’ argument in favour of oblique intent (broad view of intent)

A

strong case where the desired consequence is inseparably bound up with the foreseen (though undesired) consequence - ensures justice?

  • Arrowsmith v Jenkins: political campaigner commenced to address people on the highway and in so doing knowingly caused the highway to be blocked –> charged with wilfully obstructing the highway though her purpose was to hold a meeting
  • Brighton case of 1971: woman who inserted strychnine into a chocolate and attempted to administer it to V - inserted same drug into a batch of chocolates to shift blame/prove her innocence