mens rea Flashcards
when is a defendant taken to have intended a result?
- if it was his/her aim or purpose, and
- if the result was foreseen as virtually certain to occur as a result of the defendant’s actions and
- the defendant realised this
when will defendants be found to be reckless?
if they appreciated that because of their actions there was a chance that the result might occur, and it was unreasonable for them to act as they did
when will a defendant be found to be negligent?
if she/he behaved in a way that a reasonable person would not. it is rare for negligence to count as sufficient mens rea
what happens if a defendant is found to be voluntarily intoxicated?
the defendant will be found to have been reckless. if, though intoxicated, the defendant intended the result, s/he will still be held to have the requisite mens rea
what is the definition of intention?
normal meaning - purpose/aim.
- Lord Bridge in R v Moloney (1985)
- R v Wright (2000)
- R v Ogunbowale (2007)
but in exceptional borderline cases the jury can be directed that they are entitled to find intention if a result was virtually certain to occur and the defendant realised it was virtually certain to occur
- R v Hales (2005)
jury will need to be persuaded beyond reasonable doubt
R v Haigh (2010) - clear evidence D had smothered her child, but no evidence as to how or in what circumstances she had done this. because it wasn’t clear beyond reasonable doubt that she had murdered her child, she could only be found guilty of manslaughter and not murder
what is the test for seeing whether a result was the purpose of the defendant?
Antony Duff’s test of failure: had the result not occured, would the defendant regard himself as having failed in his plan?
- but where a result is a means to achieve a desired end, it has to be treated with caution
what should intention be distinguished from?
foresight, motive and premeditation
distinguishing intention and foresight
- in relation to core meaning - whether the defendant’s act was likely to produce the consequence is irrelevant
- but many commentators also accept that if the defendant believes that it is impossible for his action to cause the result, he cannot be said to intend it, however much he may have wanted the result to occur
- foresight of a consequence is not the same as intention, but it is evidence from which a jury may infer or find intention
Lord Scarman in *Hancock and Shankland *(1986)
the greater the probability of a consequence the more likely it is that the consequence was foreseen and…if that consequence was foreseen the greater the probability is that the consequence was also intended…[T]he probability, however high, of a consequence is only a factor
distinguishing intention and motive
Moloney (1985): “intention is something quite different from motive or desire”
- possible to intend something without wanting it to happen, and having foreseen it
Hales (2005)
D ran over a police officer in his car in attempting to escape from an arrest - not his motive to kill the police officer, but he was (as Keene LJ explained) “prepared to kill in order to escape” and therefore intended to kill
intention and premeditation
a person can act instinctively in the heat of the moment and yet intend to kill - shouldn’t be thought that a person can intend a result only if s/he has carefully formulated a plan as to how to produce that result
Woollin (1999)
Confirms the Nedrick approach: to establish intent the defendant’s actions must have been virtually certain to have caused the consequence, and the defendant must have appreciated that such was the case.
- jury may find indirect intention, i.e. the intention of the person who does not aim or need to kill or even to cause grievous bodily harm to anyone but nonetheless takes (what he knows to be) an outrageously high risk of doing so, if the result of the defendant’s action was virtually certain to be death or grievous bodily harm (objective test), and the defendant personally foresaw this (subjective test)
what is the chart for deciding whether a defendant has intention?
was it the result of the defendant’s purpose?
- yes: he intended it
- no: move to the next question
was the result a virtually certain result of his actions and did the defendant realise that the result was a virtually certain result of his actions?
- no: he didn’t intend the result
problems with Woollin
- must the jury find intention, or may the jury find intention? e.g. Court of Appeal in Matthews (2003) made it clear that it was a misdirection for a judge to tell a jury that if a result was foreseen as virtually certain then they must find intention, but then went on to say that there would be certain situations (including the case itself) where it wold be “irresistable” for the jury
- jury can take any factor they deem relevant into account (but isn’t this throwing the scope a little too wide?)
- Lord Steyn provides no justification for his changing of the word ‘infer’ to ‘find’ - why?
- does Woollin apply to just murder, or to all crimes requiring proof of intention?
Moloney (1985)
- D and stepfather engaged on long drinking spree - then decided to engage in a shooting competition to see who could load and fire a gun the fastest - D won, but in so doing shot his stepfather dead
- held not guilty for murder (but for manslaughter). defence in this case wasn’t the intoxication, but that he lacked mens rea (of which the intoxication was evidence)
- established that a person can have intention, where they did not want the result but merely foresaw it.
Cunningham recklessness
- the defendant was aware that there was a risk that his/her conduct would cause a particular result AND
- the risk was an unreasonable one for the defendant to take
Byrne J: “the accused has foreseen that the particular kind of harm might be done and yet has gone on to take the risk of it”
note that the risk doesn’t have to be obvious to the reasonable man - just the defendant. recall Stephenson (1979) - schizophrenic man set fire to a haystack, but because of his illness he didn’t realise that in lighting a match there would be danger to the haystack
R v Parker (1977)
upheld R v Briggs (1977), amending definition to say “a man is reckless in the sense required when he carries out a deliberate act knowing or closing his mind to the obvious fact that there is some risk of damage arising from that act but nevertheless continuing in performance of that act”
Lane LJ: “in the view of this court, that type of action, that type of deliberate closing of the mind, is the equivalent of knowledge and a man certainly cannot escape the consequences of his actions in this particular set of circumstances by saying ‘i never directed my mind to the obvious consequences because i was in a self-induced state of temper’”
Brady (2007)
affirmed that it’s merely enough for the defendant to have foreseen *a *risk, didn’t necessarily have to be obvious and significant
Caldwell recklessness
will be guilty if
- aware of a risk OR
- there was an obvious and serious risk AND they failed to consider whether or not there was a risk
approved in R v Lawrence (1982), but confirmed abolished by Attorney-General’s Reference (No 3 of 2003)
difference between cunningham and caldwell
caldwell included defendants who weren’t aware of an obvious risk - punished those who failed to notice a risk which would’ve been obvious to a reasonable person
- unfairly penalises those who fail to appreciate a risk they are incapable of foreesing
- Elliot v C (1983)
R v G and R (2003)
defendant must be shown to have subjectively appreciated a risk to the health or property of another but carried on in any event before they may be said to be criminally culpable. It abolished the “objective recklessness” test previously established under R v Caldwell
Bingham saw the need to modify Lord Diplock’s definition to take account of the defence of infancy, which contains the concept of “mischievous discretion”. This rule requires the court to consider the extent to which children of eight or more years are able to understand the difference between “right” and “wrong”. The Diplock test of obviousness might operate unfairly for 11- and 12-year-old boys if they were held to the same standard as reasonable adults. Bingham stated that “a person acts ‘recklessly’ with respect to:
(i) a circumstance when he is aware of a risk that it exists or will exist;
(ii) a result when he is aware of a risk that it will occur
and it is, in the circumstances known to him, unreasonable to take the risk.”
This brings the test back to a subjective standard so that defendants can be judged on the basis of their age, experience and understanding rather than on the standard of a hypothetical reasonable person who might have better knowledge and understanding.
alternatives to caldwell and cunningham
- defendants would be reckless if they are awake of a risk or failed to consider a risk which should have been obvious to a reasonable person of their age and mental abilities
- defendants would be reckless if they were aware of a risk or failed to consider an obvious risk without a good explanation –> acquittal of those who failed to see a risk due to an illness or emergency, but lead to the conviction of those who failed to see the risk due to drunkenness or anger
problems with R v G and R
- too easy for a defendant to claim that they didn’t consider a risk to others and so be entitled to acquittal
- confirmed the rules relating to intoxication - whereby a defendant who is voluntary intoxicated can be convicted without awareness of the risk. HL presented the intoxication rules as a special exception to the nromal requirement of having to prove a subjective state of mind, but given the number of crimes committed by intoxicated people it seems like the norm rather than exception