Lecture 6 Flashcards
Explaining individual acts
Instrumental rationality:
= to provide reasons for action
Three important issues:
1. How we explain behaviour
2. The role of instrumentalism in social science
3. Differentiating agents from actors
➔ Instrumental rationality focusses on agents as an abstract concept
2. Explaining individual acts
E.g., the happiness of young parents (de Bruin)
Q: How to explain individual choices with regard to having a child?
- Through instrumental rationality (“explanation”)?
- Then you expect parents to make lists of pros and cons: what makes you happy and
what hinders you?
o Individuals are then seen as agents who make assessments that can be
expressed in “laws”.
o Recall logical positivism / Popper hypothetical-deductive method
But is this the whole story?
- Or is there some sort of “basic feeling” involved, connected with values and norms
that are embedded in the communities where young parents belong to?
- It’s not just a matter of rational consideration; it is a meaningful act of actors that
takes place in a certain context formed by rules.
o Recall Schutz, Taylor, Geertz:
o Common-sense thinking (of the subjects at group level)
o Social scientific models of motivations, feelings, meanings
Hempel’s Covering Law Model (CLM)
- There is a phenomenon A that must be explained:
o The explanandum (“what has to be explained”) aka
the effect.
o = what is to be explained (effect) - How? Explain A by specifying (i) a general law and (ii) an
initial condition:
o The explanans (“that which explains”)
o = what does the explaining (law = cause) - The explanans in the CLM need to have a law: otherwise it
isn’t a scientific explanation and it wouldn’t fit in to the
positivist worldview.
According to Hempel: “(i) a law and (ii) the initial conditions logically
entail the event A to be explained.”
CLM is another name for the deductive-nomological method - (the hypothetical-deductive method is one variation of that)
E.g., of CLM: ‘broken bottles - ’On Monday morning we find bottles left outside are broken (A).
o (A) must be explained and is therefore the explanandum.
General law: if the temperature is below a certain value, glass bottles will break.
Initial condition: it has frozen hard enough on Sunday night to shatter the bottles. - Phenomenon (A) can be explained on the basis of (i) general law and (ii) this
specific initial condition
.
.
Hempel
In this model, the outbreak of WWI is explained in the same way as the shattering of the
bottles.
- In both cases, the method to explain by laws is limited to general aspects of the
events to be explained.
- In other words, intentional actions also belong to the phenomena explained by the
CLM.
- According to Hempel, a reason is a special kind of cause.
For the explanans to successfully explain the explanandum several conditions must be met
Deductive conditions:
- The explanandum must be a logical consequence of the explanans and, the sentences
constituting the explanans must be true
- Nomological (lawful) condition
- The explanans must contain at least one “law of nature” (more info on the next slide)
- This must be an essential premise in the derivation in a sense that: the derivation of
the explanandum would not be valid if this premise were removed
Causes and reasons
The ‘I’ –two perspectives: a paradox?
Recall discussion of Descartes and the subject-object distinction:
➢ The ‘I’ as embodied subject: an observable object of knowledge, a material being.
➢ The ‘I’ as pure reason: the perspective under which I experience myself, the elusive
center of my self-awareness.
Descartes could not reconcile this dualism
Positivists tried to reduce/explain away the mind/subject (there is just this physical world)
How can a person act freely in a world where everything is subjected to the law of cause
and effect?
According to Kant, this is not a contradiction but a paradox, because people appear under
two different perspectives:
- The material body is subject to the laws of nature in which causal relationships take
central stage. - Our mentality -apart from the laws of nature -is a free being, where causes give way
to reasons.
Causes and reasons are not the same; they refer to different aspects of reality!
Kant: don’t substitute causes for reasons, and vice versa!
• Causes -> empirical regularities (about, for example, exploding bottles at a certain
temperature) and predictions. No reference is required to motives and meanings.
• Reasons -> principles of action (which always refer to intentions), psychological and
social regularities (exceptions possible). Reasons are subjective.
Reasons are related to rules of conduct that can be violated, while causal laws always apply
(Winch/Risjord).
2 level of reasons:
Hempel: CLM considers ‘intentions’ and ‘reasons’ as causes that refer to general laws. - Winch: reasons are not causes; reasons refer to socially determined rules.
Davidson: what is the primary reason for an action? - The primary reason for an action is always described in causal terms!
- Therefore, “the primary reason for an action is its cause.”
- But such causes do NOT refer to laws!
Hempel, Winch and Davidson on reasons
Hempel: CLM considers ‘intentions’ and ‘reasons’ as causes that refer to general laws.
Winch: reasons are not causes; reasons refer to socially determined rules.
Davidson: what is the primary reason for an action?
- The primary reason for an action is always described in causal terms!
- Therefore, “the primary reason for an action is its cause.”
- But such causes do NOT refer to laws!
- Synthesizes aspects of Hempel / Winch
Davidson’s theory of action is closely tied to rational choice theory
- Uses tools of folk psychology (belief and desires) to understand reasons
- But Davidson is not committed to instrumental rationality
Rational Choice Theory (RCT)
Goals and beliefs are translated into preferences.
- Preferences are translated into utility functions that organize preferences from high
to low.
- Preferences are expressed in values (ordinal numbers) and the optimum choice is
calculated.
RCT main assumptions
Humans are perfect rational beings
- Their preferences are completely ordered by priority.
- They have complete information about choices and outcomes.
- They can perfectly determine the optimum choice.
Connections with the notion of instrumental rationality
- RCT is about instrumental rationality
o Preferences are the translation of supposed motives and reasons.
o No empirical research is conducted into the actual reasons that people have
for their behaviour.
RCT: decision theory, game theory, social choice theory, and other micro-economic
applications
Dominant strategy
- An optimal strategy for a player, without being dependent on the strategy of other players Nash equilibrium - A situation nobody can do better by changing his choice
Dominant stratedy and nash equilibrium
Kenney has no dominant strategy:
- There is no optimal strategy that is not dependent on the strategy of Imamura.
Imamura has a dominant strategy:
- Always play ‘north’
There is one “Nash equilibrium”:
- Imamura and Kennedy play North:
- Nobody can do better by changing their choice unilaterally.
Challenges for rational choice theory:
Are human beings rational? Is the underlying view of man plausible?
➢ Balancing preferences presupposes the ideal of (psychological) autonomy. Is this
tenable?
➢ Too much focus on an “I-centered conception of agency”?
➢ Sometimes the rational act is not the right act
Preferences, autonomy, and rationality
Q: Do we have all the needed information to make a choice?
Example: selecting a healthcare plan
This assumes we (as rational agents) can:
➢ Acquire information
➢ Understand information
➢ Know how to value information
➢ Make a choice based on information
➢ Act in accordance with preferences formed..
Sometimes the rational act is not the right act
RCT: It is always avbout my preferences. My preferences do not necessarily have to be
selfish!
Sen’s Distinction between:
- Sympathy: one’s interests are acknowledged, and these interests correspond to your
own interests.
- Commitment: you confirm one’s choice, even if this goes against your own interest.
Against RCT: we need to quantify the utilities in a better way!
But behavioral experiments (e.g., Guala) show that motivation is complicated…
Chapter 5 book – Action and Agency
Explaining Action
Admiral Tryon and Instrumental rationality
Understanding the motivations of historical figures is often an important aspect of
understanding the events of which they were part
E.g., → Vice-Admiral George Tryon, commander of the British Mediterranean fleet, ordered
two iron-clad battleships equipped with rams to turn toward each other. They collided,
sinking the Victoria. What was he thinking?
➢ Many hypotheses why he did what he did
No one will ever know for sure what Tryon’s intentions were when he gave the order which
resulted in the sinking of the Victoria. Individual theories can start and end with the possible
interpretations of those five words he spoke on the chart house: “It was all my fault”
➢ As a first pass at the idea of an action explanation we might say that the explanation
of an intentional action presents the agent’s reasons, and these reasons make the
action instrumentally rational. Intentional action explanations are not causal because
a causal explanation does not assume that its subject is instrumentally rational.
➢ With respect to naturalism, the concern with agents and actions means that the
social sciences require a different form of explanation than the natural sciences. With
respect to reductionism, the concern with intentional action means that there is
something special about the level of agency.
The Function of General Laws in History
Any attempt to contrast the forms of explanation in the natural sciences with the social
sciences requires some conception of “explanation.”
→ The Victoria sank because water entered the ship, which made it at some point
impossible to stay floating = General law (fits into lawful pattern or regularity)