Historic Injustice Flashcards
What does Butt (2009) say about forward looking approaches?
Forward-looking approaches may result in only a limited recognition of the ethical significance of past interaction and may resist the rectification of historic injustice that do not have effects on people living today, as for these approaches the significance of historic distributions lies in the way in which they contribute towards individuals’ legitimate expectations today so there may be no reason to seek to restore the earlier distribution outside of its relation to the current unjust distribution.
In what ways, according to Butt (2009) are current generations linked to past wrongdoings of their political communities?
Three ways in which current generations within particular political communities may be linked, in a morally relevant way to past wrongdoing:
- Benefit: When one community is benefiting, and another is disadvantaged, as a result of the automatic effects of an act of historic injustice
- Entitlement: when one community has possession of property to which another is morally entitled
- Responsibility: When one community is responsible for an ongoing injustice in relation to another community, understood in terms of an ongoing failure to fulfil rectificatory duties over time.
My claim is that, taken together, these morally relevant forms of connection mean that those living in the developed world possess significant rectificatory duties to many of those in less developed countries. They are complementary but distinct bases for modern day rectificatory duties.
What case does Nehisi-Coates (2014) make for reparations?
Nehisi-Coates points out the way in which Black people in the US remain handicapped both by a lack of wealth and a restricted choice of neighbourhood that is the result of a long history of slavery, racist laws and policies, and social structures
For example, black people were excluded from most legitimate means of obtaining a mortgage by redlining which “went beyond FHA-backed loans and spread to the entire mortgage industry, which was already rife with racism”.
Nehisi-Coates emphasises how governmental embrace of segregation combined with the racism of white citizens to worsen effects when white neighbourhoods formed block associations for the purpose of enforcing segregation, turned to racial violence when government and private banks were not effective enough, and fled the neighbourhood when this failed in what Nehisi-Coates describes as a “triumph of social engineering”
In the present, Chicago’s impoverished black neighbourhoods remain poor to the extent that they are “ecologically distinct”
Reparations that redistributed wealth would seek to close the wealth gap which illustrates the enduring legacy of a history of treating black people as sub-citizens, and sub-humans.
Reparations would involve a national reckoning that would lead to a spiritual renewal; the history of racial injustice permeates many issues such as healthcare, education, and housing which needs to be dealt with
How does Lu describe structural injustice and how, according to Lu (2011) is colonialism a structural injustice?
Structural injustices pervert systems of norms, legitimizing individual wrongdoing.
Coloniser states actions were typically not aberrant violations of international norms, customs, or laws; they happened against unjust baselines.
Most cases of social and political injustice can be analysed on the two levels of the direct causal relationship between individual agents and the injustice, and the social structural processed that enable/encourage this wrongdoing.
According to a structural approach, moral responsibility for wrongful acts can certainly be attributed to the colonizing state and culpable individuals, but some share of historical responsibility should also be attributed to all states, especially the dominant ones, that contributed to perpetuating the unjust social structures of a colonial international system.
Why does a structural analysis of colonial injustice not support a simplistic division of colonizers and colonized into perpetrator and victim roles, according to Lu (2011)?
Among colonized populations, individuals and groups occupy different social positions in the structure of colonial domination, and some may use their relatively privileged position and resources to dominate others and may even derive some benefits from participation in colonial enterprises at the expense of their more socially vulnerable compatriots. Another hallmark of structural injustice, then, is its propensity to produce victim-perpetrators: those in colonial positions of subordination (such as all Korean colonial subjects) nevertheless still occupied different social positions that enabled some (for example, private Korean entrepreneurs engaged in the commercial sex industry or human trafficking) to derive benefits at the expense of their more socially vulnerable compatriots (such as impoverished Korean women and girls).
Who should be held responsible for structural injustice, according to Lu (2014)?
A structural analysis reveals that the international society of states, in enacting through its rules, customs and practices a colonial international system, bears some historical responsibility for the unjust international social structures that enabled state wrongdoing.
Acknowledging colonial injustices as structural injustices generates a “political responsibility” to effect structural reforms.
Argues, with Young, that non-culpable agents who contribute to the production of unjust structural conditions bear political responsibility to reform their social practices so that they produce more just outcomes.
The justness of the outcomes or social conditions that result from structural reform must include the elimination of social disadvantages that identifiable victims may suffer because of past injustice.
While legal changes can go a long way toward establishing just social conditions, reparations for victims who continue to experience disadvantages resulting from past structural injustices is also necessary for realizing, in practice, the patterns of social relations that define a just international society. In a political responsibility framework, the ground for providing reparations to victims is not that contemporary agents are liable in amorally culpable way for historical colonial injustices. Rather, contemporary agents bear political responsibility to correct inherited structural injustices, and reparative measures that enable former victims to exercise effective political and social agency constitute one requirement for social structures to be considered just.
Why should we have backward-looking justifications according to McKeown (2021)?
McKeown argues that there is value in making backward looking reparations claims based on state liability, drawing on the Caribbean Community’s (CARICOM’s) 10-Point Plan for reparations to illustrate how forward and backward-looking reparation demands can be made with solely backward-looking justifications
There is a moral case that reparations are owed based solely on historical injustices themselves because there were crimes against humanity committed.
Retaining focus on past ensures that the particular liability and obligations of particular states and agents are recognised and prevents governments from evading their outstanding historical reparative obligations by ‘focusing on the future’.
Acknowledging backwards-looking liability will be to listen to the claims of the communities who have suffered the consequences of the injustices and to recognise the wrongs committed.
There can be backward-looking justifications for forward-looking reparations; there are backward-looking justifications for some forward-looking demands in the 10-point CARICOM reparation plan.
What is McKeown’s (2021) response to the counterfactual problem?
Claims for reparations on backward-looking principles do not necessarily seek restoration to a state prior to the injustice or to a state that would have been had the injustice not occurred. For example, the Caribbean Community 10-Point Plan for reparation, which according to McKeown has “fundamentally backward-looking” justifications for reparations as the justifications are based on the wrongs done in the past, makes claims which do not aim to redistribute resources to restore Caribbean peoples to where they would have been had the crimes against them not been committed.
Why, according to McKeown (2021) can states be held liable?
Since states can be seen as morally responsible agents because they are more than the sum of their constituent members, they have internal decision-making structure, they have identities over time, and the group is self-asserting, they can be capable of bearing responsibilities and can reason and take purposeful action
What does McKeown (2021) say about the structural injustice model?
The structural injustice approach reveals the limitations of CARICOM’s proposal as the state-to-CARICOM approach occludes the responsibility of other actors that might bear reparative responsibilities, including bystander states, corporations, and collaborators with slavery within victim states.
But the structural injustice view not only exposes the limitations of CARICOM’s plan, I argue it also provides resources for improving it. It exposes the need to tackle structural injustice in the international order that maintains the marginalisation of the region.
The social connection model approach does not claim that descendants of slave owners, or all white people, are somehow guilty for living off the inheritance of unjustly acquired wealth. European citizens cannot be held responsible on the liability model, because it is not reasonable to claim that they personally bear liability for the crimes committed; they were not alive at the time of the crimes and played no role in them. However, on the social connection model, European citizens’ connection to persisting structural injustice generates political responsibility to try to overcome it. Thus, European states bear backward-looking liability for reconciling their past transgressions. On my view, the responsibility to pay for this burden can be transferred to citizens in the way that all burdens acquired by the state transfer to citizens, whether or not the state met our contemporary standards of legitimacy at the time. If this justification is rejected, it can still be argued that contemporary European citizens share a forward-looking political responsibility to support reparations on the grounds that they are connected to structural injustice in the Caribbean and therefore share political responsibility to create a better present and future in the region.
Why, according to Nuti (2019) should we “de-termporalise injustice”?
Nuti argues for de-temporalising injustice– that is, refusing to separate, in certain cases, the past from the present. Ongoing injustices should be theoretically and normatively conceptualised as the reproduction of unjust history under new circumstances and through changes.
Unjust history should normatively matter in considerations about justice because injustices are reproduced over time, and unjust history shapes the background conditions in which present injustices occur and relations between agents are established in the present. This means that some ongoing injustices should be theoretically and normatively conceptualised as the reproduction of unjust history under new circumstances and through changes, as opposed to being seen as separate from the past
What should the process of redress look like, according to Nuti (2019)?
Three required (yet not exhaustive) forms of interventions that should be undertaken in the process of redress: reparations, transformative policy making and counter-historical institutional interventions.
The process of redress should thus entail a backward looking normative analysis holding contemporary powerful agents morally responsible for their significant contribution to the reproduction of an unjust history over time and thus accountable to repair their ‘structural debt’. Reparations demands should be pursued through a participatory approach, which sees claimants at the forefront of the mobilisation and decision-making process. As the activist politics of reparations shows,1 reparations demands usually are both ‘redistributive’ (e.g. free and public educational programmes, a guaranteed minimum liveable income and affirmative actions) and about ‘recognition. That said, reparations should be complemented by other (more for ward-looking) interventions. This is not only because sometimes move ments fighting for historical and structural inequalities do not seem to put reparations on their agenda or reparations may not be as successful as initially hoped at repairing unjust historical structures, but also because redressing the new reproduction of an unjust history calls for an ongoing commitment to preventing its possible ‘reactivation’ and remodelling our background conditions (also through institutional innovation).
In what way does Nuti criticise Lu?
Lu’s understanding mistakenly grounds responsibility on the allegedly equal contribution all agents participating in structures make to their sustainment, overlooking differences among different types of agents within structures and the different power agents display in their contributions
Some agents inherently have a significant capacity to influence structural processes due to their features of the role the occupy in society/internationally. These agents should therefore be held responsible for acting/failing to act in a way which reinforces structural injustice.
Who should be held responsible for structural injustice, according to Nuti (2019)?
No agent, as powerful as they may be, can on their own transform unjust structures. However, some agents inherently have a significant capacity to influence structural processes in virtue of their features (e.g. states) or the role they occupy in a society or internationally (e.g. the US president), and they possess this capacity independently of whether they choose to use it.
If we take structural injustice (and, especially, injustice that is the new reproduction of an unjust history) seriously, we should pay particular attention to relations and mutually constituted positions within structures and offer an account of political responsibility that is deeply sensitive to them.
Those who are privileged by certain structures have the political responsibility to contributing to eradicating them.
What is the principle of wrongful benefits, according to Pasternak (2016)
The “principle of wrongful benefits” refers to the duties of agents who benefit from an original wrongdoing; agents can either just benefit from a wrongdoing or can benefit and contribute to it, and agents can either voluntarily or non-voluntarily benefit from this wrongdoing.