Exam 1 Flashcards

1
Q

Bentham, an English moral philosopher and legal reformer, founded the doctrine of utilitarianism.

A

.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
2
Q

The highest principle of morality is to maximize happiness, the overall balance of pleasure over pain.

A

utilitarianism

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
3
Q

Utility

A

whatever produces pleasure or happiness, and whatever prevents pain or suffering.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
4
Q

Bentham: We are all governed by the feelings of pain and pleasure. They are our “sovereign masters.” They govern us in everything we do and also determine what we ought to do. The standard of right and wrong is “fastened to their throne.”

A

.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
5
Q

a prison with a central inspection tower that would enable the supervisor to observe the inmates without their seeing him.run by a private contractor (ideally himself), who would manage the prison in exchange for the profits to be made from the labor of the convicts, who would work sixteen hours per day.

A

Panopticon

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
6
Q

The Runaway Trolley Case
(quotations are from Sandel’s book, pp. 21-24)
1. Some factual differences between version #1 and version #2 of “the runaway trolley” case:
a. In #1, I am the “driver” of the trolley car; in #2 I am an “onlooker.”
b. In #1, there is a sidetrack; in #2, there is no sidetrack.
c. In #1, there is one worker on the sidetrack who is killed; in #2, there is “a very heavy man” on a bridge overlooking the track who is killed.

A

..

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
7
Q

“Why does the principle that seems right in the first case – sacrifice one life to save five – seem wrong in the second?” In short what is the moral difference between these cases?

A

a. It does seem cruel to push a man to his death, even for a good cause.
“But is it any less cruel to kill a man by crashing into him with a trolley car?”
b. In the pushing case (version 2) the heavy man hasn’t consented to being pushed onto the track; he didn’t choose to be involved.
“But the same could be said of the man working on the side track.” He hasn’t consented to being killed either.
c. In the “driver” case (version 1) you are not intending the track worker’s death, even though it is foreseeable?
“But the same is true in the pushing case. The death of the man you push off the bridge is not essential to your purpose. All he needs to do is block the trolley; if he can do so and somehow survive, you would be delighted.”

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
8
Q

There are philosophers who would disagree with Sandel’s claim that in the “pushing” case you are not intending the death of the heavy man. In her account of the Doctrine of Double Effect in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Alison McIntyre writes that
“It would be wrong to throw someone into the path of a runaway trolley in order to stop it and keep it from hitting five people on the track ahead; that would involve intending harm to the one as a means of saving the five. But it would be permissible to divert a runaway trolley onto a track holding one and away from a track holding five: in that case one foresees the death of the one as a side effect of saving the five but one does not intend it.”
McIntyre also points out that some philosophers “deny that the distinction between intended and merely foreseen consequences has moral significance….” What if a soldier “throws himself on the grenade in order to shield his fellow soldiers from the force of an explosion?” Does it make sense to say that he does not intend “to sacrifice his own life in order to save the others,” that he “merely foresees that his life will end as a side effect of his action?” MacIntyre claims that “many have argued that this is an implausible description of the soldier’s action and that his action is permissible even if he does intend to cause his own death as a means to save the others.”

A

..

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
9
Q
  1. Sandel then asks whether the two versions of the runaway trolley case should be governed by the same principle, namely, “we should sacrifice one life to save five.” After all “both involve a deliberate choice to take the life of one innocent person to prevent a greater loss of life.”
A

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
10
Q
  1. Sandel claims that “it is not easy to explain the moral difference between these cases – why turning the trolley seems right, but pushing the man off the bridge seems wrong.”
    Some moral dilemmas (such as the one in the “runaway trolley case”) come about as a result of conflicting moral principles or rules:
    “we should save as many vs. “it is wrong to kill an innocent lives as possible” person, even for a good cause”
    Here we must ask: “Which principle has greater weight, or is more appropriate under the circumstances?”
A

,,,

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
11
Q

Consequentialist theories of moral obligation claim that the moral rightness or wrongness of an individual action depends on the consequences of the action or the rule under which the action falls. Suppose Smith lies about Jones and, as a consequence, injures Jones’s reputation and Mary breaks her promise to Jane and, as a consequence, undermines Jane’s trust in Mary. The consequentialist thinks that Smith’s lying about Jones is wrong because it injures Jones’s reputation and Mary’s breaking her promise to Jane is wrong because it undermines Jane’s trust in Mary

A

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
12
Q

The following statements convey a consequentialist point of view:

A

“It is morally right to keep a promise because it fosters trust between people.”
“It is morally right for me to show equal consideration for the interests of my employees because, in the long run, it serves my interests.”
“Cruelty to animals is morally wrong because it makes a person value other human beings less.”

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
13
Q

Nonconsequentialist theories of moral obligation claim that the moral rightness or wrongness of an action does not depend on the consequences. Something other than the consequences makes the action right or wrong. The action may be wrong in itself, or wrong because it is unnatural, or wrong because it is forbidden by God, etc. If Smith’s act of lying is wrong, it is not wrong because it injures Jones’ reputation and if Mary’s act of breaking her promise to Jane is wrong, it is not because it undermines Jane’s trust in Mary. In principle, a nonconsequentialist must hold that an action may be morally right even though all of its consequences are bad and that an action may be morally wrong even though all of its consequences are good.

A

,,,,

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
14
Q

The following statements convey a nonconsequentialist point of view:

A

“Lying is morally wrong because it is intrinsically evil, wrong in itself.”
“Stealing is morally wrong because it is forbidden by God.”
“Suicide is morally wrong because it is contrary to the natural inclination to preserve life.”
Clear examples of a nonconsequentialist theory are the divine command theory and the natural law theory. Probably the clearest example of a consequentialist theory is utilitarianism.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
15
Q
  1. Many people see a natural association between morality and religion. God’s law is thought to be the ultimate foundation of morality. The Ten Commandments are part and parcel of the Judaeo-Christian heritage.
A

The Divine Command Theory

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
16
Q

“an action or kind of action is right or wrong if and only if and because it is commanded or forbidden by God, or, in other words, that what ultimately makes an action right or wrong is its being commanded or forbidden by God and nothing else.”

A

voluntaristic version of the DCT

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
17
Q

“Does God command or forbid this action?” If He commands it, then it is the right thing to do; if He forbids it, then it is the wrong thing to do. His commanding it makes the action right; his forbidding it makes it wrong. No appeal to the consequences of the act is made here. The action is right or wrong irrespective of the consequences of the act. So the DCT is a nonconsequentialist theory of moral obligation.

A

,,,

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
18
Q

Julia Driver cites three examples of divine commands found in the Bible :

A

The Abraham-Isaac story (Genesis 22:1-2) God commands Abraham to kill his son Isaac as a test of faith.
God commands the Israelites to plunder and loot the belongings of the Egyptians (Exodus 11: 2).
God commands Hosea to engage in sexual intercourse with an adulteress (Hosea 3: 1).

19
Q

In the voluntaristic version “God’s will is necessary and sufficient in determining the content of morality—it actually defines it… God’s will is necessary in that if an act is not in compliance with God’s will regarding the right, it is not the right action. God’s will is sufficient in that all that is required for an act to be ‘right’ is that God wills it to be right.” (p. 25)

A

..

20
Q

What are some of the major objections to voluntaristic version of the divine command theory?

A

a. Some people object to the theory because they believe
we are unable know God’s will and, therefore, what He commands or forbids. Access to the Divine Will is a problem for them.
b. The Euthyphro objection – In one of Plato’s dialogues entitled Euthyphro, Socrates raises the following question:
“Is an act right (a) because God commands it or (b) does he command it because it is right?”

21
Q

Socrates claims that if God commands something because it is right, then Euthyphro must abandon the Divine Command theory. But why? Well if God commands something because it is (already) right, then it is right whether or not God commands it and thus it does not become right because God commands it.

A

22
Q

James Rachels claims that we can avoid the difficulty if we adopt the second of Socrates’ alternatives: rather than saying that an action is right because God commands it, we should say instead that God commands an action because it is right. If we say that God commands us to do an action because it is right, we may then also
6
say that “God, who is infinitely wise, recognizes that truthfulness is better than deceitfulness, and so he commands us to be truthful; he sees that killing is wrong, and so he commands us not to kill; and so on for all the moral rules.” (See James Rachels, The Elements of Moral Philosophy, 4th edition, McGraw Hill, 2003, p. 52)

A

23
Q

Ralph Cudworth’s famous objection – According to Frankena Cudworth argues that if the divine command theory is true, then, “if God were to command cruelty, dishonesty, or injustice, these things would be right and obligatory.”

A

24
Q

Rachels helps us to understand Cudworth’s objection. He claims that if we say “conduct is right because God commands it,” then God’s commands end up being “arbitrary.” In Exodus 20:16 He commands us to be truthful. God’s commanding truthfulness is the reason why telling the truth is the right thing to do. Apart from God’s commanding it, “truth telling is neither good nor bad.” (p. 51) But couldn’t He also have commanded us to lie, and if He did, then lying would be the right thing to do.
The most common reply to this objection is that God would never command cruelty, etc., because He is by nature good and that a good being would never command cruelty.

A

25
Q

The Doxastic Version of the DCT

According to Julia Driver this version says that

A

“morality depends upon what God believes is right and wrong… God is, in effect, an ideal observer…. He is impartial, since he loves all persons equally; He is rational and thus makes no errors of reasoning; and He has full information, so He will not be making mistakes on the basis of partial information. If God, then, who is not swayed by bias or prejudice, who is completely fair, and who knows all of the relevant facts believes that x is wrong, then x is wrong.” (p. 27)
If you reject the voluntaristic version of the divine command theory, then presumably you could accept the doxastic version of the divine command theory.

26
Q

Driver sees a problem with the doxastic version: “if God
7
believes that 2 + 3, = 19”, then it is true that “2 + 3 = 19… this can be extended to moral claims… if God believes that torturing kittens for fun is permissible, then it is permissible.” (p. 27)

A

27
Q

Act Utilitarianism (AU) says that we should look to the utility of the individual act in order to determine an act’s rightness or wrongness. Assume for the moment that good = pleasure = happiness and evil = pain = unhappiness. Act utilitarianism asks, “Does the individual act produce the greatest possible balance of pleasure over pain, happiness over suffering, for all those in any way affected by the act?” If an individual act of lying produces a greater balance of happiness over suffering, then it is morally right; if it produces a greater balance of suffering over happiness, then it is morally wrong.

A

28
Q

Rule Utilitarianism (RU) says that we should look to the utility of the rule in order to determine the individual act’s rightness or wrongness. In other words, we should ask “What rule will produce the greatest possible balance of pleasure over pain, happiness over suffering for all those in any way affected by the rule?” So a right act is one that conforms to (does not violate) a rule. Given the rule that says “We ought to keep our promises,” then when faced with a situation where I have a choice between breaking a promise or keeping a promise, I ought to keep the promise, even if keeping it would produce more bad consequences than good consequences.

A

….

29
Q

Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832) follows the consequentialist approach. He is the founder of Utilitarianism, whose main idea is that “the highest principle of morality is to maximize happiness, the overall balance of pleasure and pain. According to Bentham, the right thing to do is whatever will maximize utility. By ‘utility,’ he means whatever produces pleasure or happiness, and whatever prevents pain or suffering.”

A

30
Q

According to Bentham pleasure and pain are “our sovereign masters.” They determine everything we as individuals ought to do. “The standard of right and wrong are ‘fastened to their throne.’” It is important to note that, for Bentham, “maximizing utility is a principle not only for individuals but also for legislators. In deciding what law or policies to enact, a government should do whatever will maximize the happiness of the community as a whole.” A cost/benefit analysis should govern the enactment of laws and social policies as well as the ethical behavior of individuals.

A

..

31
Q

How Strong is the pleasure?

A

INTENSITY

32
Q

How long does the pleasure last?

A

DURATION

33
Q

How certain is the occurrence of the pleasure?

A

CERTAINTY OR UNCERTAINTY

34
Q

How close is the pleasure?

A

PROPINQUITY OR REMOTENESS

35
Q

How fruitful is the pleasure? Pleasures that are fruitful are those that lead to other pleasures.

A

FECUNDITY

36
Q

How pure is the pleasure? Pleasures that are pure are those that are free of any pains (i.e., not mixed with any pains).

A

PURITY

37
Q

What is the scope of the pleasure? How many persons will experience pleasure? (this is in line with the idea of “the greatest happiness of the greatest number”).

A

EXTENT

38
Q

Bentham thinks that there are “no possible grounds” for
rejecting the principle that we should maximize utility. People who claim to believe in individual rights and duties must, ultimately, justify them by an appeal to the principle of utility. “They would have no basis for defending these duties or rights unless they believed that respecting them would maximize happiness, at least in the long run.”

A

.

39
Q

Bentham believes that all debates and disagreements focus on how to apply the principle of utility, not on the principle itself.

A

,,

40
Q
  1. Bentham wanted utilitarianism to serve “as the basis of political reform.” For example, he was interested in making “penal policy more efficient and humane” (Panopticon example) and in “pauper management” (beggars example).
A

.

41
Q

“pauper management”—improve it “by establishing a self–financing workhouse for the poor.” Bentham “sought to reduce the presence of beggars on the street.”

A

.

42
Q

Bentham’s observation: “encountering beggars on

the streets reduces the happiness of passersby, in two ways.”

A

(1) “for tenderhearted souls, the sight of a beggar produces the pain of sympathy.”
(2) “for hardhearted folk, it generates the pain of disgust.”

43
Q

“The most glaring weakness of utilitarianism, many argue, is that it fails to respect individual rights. By caring only about the sum of satisfactions, it can run roughshod over individual people. For the utilitarian, individuals matter, but only in the sense that each person’s preferences should be counted along with everyone else’s. But this means that the utilitarian logic, if consistently applied, could sanction ways of treating persons that violate what we think of as fundamental norms of decency and respect.”

A

Individual Rights

44
Q

Sandel employs three cases to illustrate the point that utilitarianism can run roughshod over the rights of individuals, namely, the case of throwing Christians to lions, the case of torturing a suspected terrorist, and the “city of happiness” case.

A

..