Epistemology Flashcards
Acquaintance knowledge
‘knowing’ in the sense of knowing a person, place, thing, sensation or feeling. e.g., knowing the taste of coffee.
Ability knowledge
knowing how to do something, may be referred to as a skill. e.g., knowing how to tie shoelaces.
Propositional knowledge
something which makes a claim about the world and reflects something about reality - something that is or something that was. e.g., knowing that it is snowing in Scotland.
Locke’s definition of knowledge
A real definition picks out the real essence of an object. For objects without a real essence a real definition cannot be seeked, always artificial to some extent.
Zagzebski’s definition of knowledge
- knowledge is a concept.
- to define this concept of knowledge as if it does have a real essence we undergo conceptual analysis.
- breaking down a concept into its various parts, by exploring what conditions are necessary for a true example of the concept to occur.
Socrates’ definition of knowledge
- believed that true belief and knowledge are not the same.
- having correct beliefs does not necessarily mean having knowledge.
- knowledge goes beyond just having correct beliefs.
- it involves a deeper understanding and justification for those beliefs.
Plato’s definition of knowledge
Considers the view ‘true belief accompanied by a rational account is knowledge’ or knowledge is a JTB (Justified True Belief).
The Tripartite View (JTB)
S knows that p if and only if:
1. S is justified in believing that p
2. p is true and
3. S believes that p
Issue with truth from JTB: are the conditions individually necessary?
knowledge changes overtime as scientific knowledge progresses, people used to think the earth was static and now we believe it is expanding.
Issue with belief from JTB: are the conditions individually necessary?
having your memory associate an answer with a question is arguably not the same as truly knowing something. In order to know something, you have to know (or at lest believe) that you know it.
Issue with justification from JTB: are the conditions individually necessary?
To know that I am having an experience of redness (looking at something red) requires no justification since it is known immediately with no process of reasoning or inference.
Infallibilism
Seeks to strengthen the justification condition in JTB to say it must be certain (no rational doubt).
Criticism - what we can know is limited.
Defence - gettier counter examples not followed by infallibilism because they involve lucky true beliefs.
No false lemmas (k = J + T + B + N)
Adds a premise to JTB:
4. It is on true grounds that S believes that P
Criticism - Fake barn county
Defence - effective in dealing with gettier cases.
Reliabilism (k = T + B + R)
S knows that p if and only if:
1. P is true
2. S believes that p is true
3. S belief that p is true is caused by a reliable method.
Criticism - faces challenges in explaining how a belief can be justified but still fail to be knowledge due to luck or coincidence.
Virtue Epistemology (k = V + T + B)
removes the justification criteria (like reliabilism) and replaces it with epistemic virtue.
Deals with gettier cases effectively by emphasising the importance of the knower’s intellectual virtue in determining whether a belief qualifies as knowledge.
Issue with JTB: are the conditions jointly sufficient?
Gettier cases demonstrate that it is possible to have justified true belief that are not considered knowledge. E.g., Jones and Smith both apply for a job, Smith is told by the director of the company that Jones will get the job. Smith counts the no. of coins in Jones pocket and counts 10 coins. From these two pieces of evidence he forms a belief that the person with 10 coins in their pocket will get the job. Smith gets the job - the director lied about Jones getting the job and Smith also happened to have 10 coins in his pocket. This is a lucky true belief, it was justified from what Smith was told by the director and the counting of the coins but it is not considered knowledge.
Direct realism
The external world exists independently of the mind. We perceive the external world directly i.e. what you see is what you get!
Issue with direct realism: perceptual variation
What we perceive are not physical objects BUT sense-data.
E.g., the table with look a different shape and colour depending on the perceiver and the angle they are perceiving the table from.
Issue with direct realism: illusions
What we perceive is not necessarily what the world is like.
E.g., a straw in water will look bent but we know that it is actually straight it’s just the water distorts the view of the straw.
Issue of direct realism: hallucinations
We can experience perceptual hallucinations: visual, auditory and olfactory.
Like illusions, hallucinations can be subjectively distinguishable from veridical perception (perceiving things as they truly are, without an distortion.)
Issue with direct realism: the time-lag argument
It takes 8 mins for light to reach earth, so when you are looking at the sun you seeing it as it was 8 mins ago. You are not perceiving the sun directly.
Indirect realism
The external world exists independently of the mind BUT we perceive the external world indirectly via sense data.
The immediate object of perception is sense data. This sense data is caused by and represents , the mind-independent external world.
Issue with indirect realism: mind independent ideas cannot be lile mind independent objects
the example of perceptual variation. As the example of when looking at a table and how it can change from looking square to looking diamond shaped suggests that my sense data changes, however in reality the table does not change. So how can sense data resemble the real world if sense data changes depending on my perception but in reality the object does not change.
Issue with indirect realism: Scepticism + the veil of perception
We have no way of telling if the sense-data we perceive is an accurate representation of the external world OR if there even is an external world.
Issue with indirect realism: The external world is the best hypothesis
Russell comes up with this and uses the example of a cat and the dwindling fire.
Berkeley could say there is no external world and the cat doesn’t exist if perceived and Russell could respond BUT Berkeley could further respond with: God perceives it so that’s why it moves places when you return to the room.
Issue with indirect realism: 2 responses to scepticism from Locke
- The involuntary nature of perception -> we can’t choose what we see, I can’t suddenly changed from seeing a white wall to a spotty wall, I don’t have that control.
- The coherence of different senses -> sense work together, I know that I am writing because I can see it, read what i’ve wrote etc. (Cockburn develops on this)